Last updated 20/06/24: Online ordering is currently unavailable due to technical issues. We apologise for any delays responding to customers while we resolve this. For further updates please visit our website: https://www.cambridge.org/news-and-insights/technical-incident

We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings .

Login Alert

strong continuity hypothesis

  • > Journals
  • > Behavioral and Brain Sciences
  • > Volume 19 Issue 4
  • > Universal Grammar and critical periods: A most amusing...

strong continuity hypothesis

Article contents

Universal grammar and critical periods: a most amusing paradox.

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 February 2010

Epstein et al. take as given that, (1) a hypothetical Universal Grammar (UG) exists that allows children effortlessly to acquire their first language; they then argue (2) that critical or sensitive periods do not block the UG from second language acquisition. Therefore, why can't we all effortlessly “acquire” Tibetan in six months or so? Data concerning the neural bases of language are also noted.

Access options

Crossref logo

This article has been cited by the following publications. This list is generated based on data provided by Crossref .

  • Google Scholar

View all Google Scholar citations for this article.

Save article to Kindle

To save this article to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle .

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Volume 19, Issue 4
  • Philip Lieberman (a1)
  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X00043727

Save article to Dropbox

To save this article to your Dropbox account, please select one or more formats and confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you used this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your Dropbox account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox .

Save article to Google Drive

To save this article to your Google Drive account, please select one or more formats and confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you used this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your Google Drive account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive .

Reply to: Submit a response

- No HTML tags allowed - Web page URLs will display as text only - Lines and paragraphs break automatically - Attachments, images or tables are not permitted

Your details

Your email address will be used in order to notify you when your comment has been reviewed by the moderator and in case the author(s) of the article or the moderator need to contact you directly.

You have entered the maximum number of contributors

Conflicting interests.

Please list any fees and grants from, employment by, consultancy for, shared ownership in or any close relationship with, at any time over the preceding 36 months, any organisation whose interests may be affected by the publication of the response. Please also list any non-financial associations or interests (personal, professional, political, institutional, religious or other) that a reasonable reader would want to know about in relation to the submitted work. This pertains to all the authors of the piece, their spouses or partners.

Breadcrumbs Section. Click here to navigate to respective pages.

On Two Hypotheses of "Transfer" in L2A: Minimal Trees and Absolute L1 Influence

On Two Hypotheses of "Transfer" in L2A: Minimal Trees and Absolute L1 Influence

DOI link for On Two Hypotheses of "Transfer" in L2A: Minimal Trees and Absolute L1 Influence

Click here to navigate to parent product.

This chapter presents evidence supporting the Strong Continuity Hypothesis in adult second language (L2) acquisition. It discusses that at all stage of acquisition, L2 learners have knowledge of the full inventory of both lexical and functional syntactic categories provided by Universal Grammar (UG). The chapter argues that the Weak Continuity Hypothesis provides a compelling alternative model of and an important possible explanation for, certain aspects of the apparent developmental trajectory of adult L2 acquisition. The Weak Continuity Hypothesis merits both empirical and theoretical evaluation. It outlines an alternative analysis of some of the specific data presented by Vainikka and Young-Scholten using the Strong Continuity Hypothesis for adult L2 acquisition. The chapter presents preliminary results of an experimental study investigating the acquisition of functional categories by adult native speakers of Japanese learning English.

  • Privacy Policy
  • Terms & Conditions
  • Cookie Policy
  • Taylor & Francis Online
  • Taylor & Francis Group
  • Students/Researchers
  • Librarians/Institutions

Connect with us

Registered in England & Wales No. 3099067 5 Howick Place | London | SW1P 1WG © 2024 Informa UK Limited

  • Corpus ID: 227263255

Universal grammar: The strong continuity hypothesis in first language acquisition.

  • Published 1999
  • Linguistics

29 Citations

The strong continuity hypothesis: evidence from arabic-speaking children data.

  • Highly Influenced

Acquisition of Functional Categories in Early Spanish: Evidence for the Strong Continuity Hypothesis

  • 23 Excerpts

Continuity and modularity in language acquisition and research

النّحو الكلّي والاكتساب الفطري لبعض المقاييس في العربيّة التونسيّة: مقاربة لسانيّة أحيائيّة لحالات عينيّة, recurrent babbling: evaluating the acquisition of grammar from limited input data, the emergence of nominal expressions in spanish-english early bilinguals, paths and places: aspects of grammar and acquisition, a constraint-based approach to child language acquisition of shona morphosyntax, multilingualism: new perspectives on syntactic development, children's knowledge of hierarchical phrase structure: quantifier floating in japanese*, related papers.

Showing 1 through 3 of 0 Related Papers

strong continuity hypothesis

1st Edition

Syntactic Theory and First Language Acquisition Cross-linguistic Perspectives -- Volume 1: Heads, Projections, and Learnability -- Volume 2: Binding, Dependencies, and Learnability

VitalSource Logo

  • Taylor & Francis eBooks (Institutional Purchase) Opens in new tab or window

Description

Universal Grammar (UG) is a theory of both the fundamental principles for all possible languages and the language faculty in the "initial state" of the human organism. These two volumes approach the study of UG by joint, tightly linked studies of both linguistic theory and human competence for language acquisition. In particular, the volumes collect comparable studies across a number of different languages, carefully analyzed by a wide range of international scholars. The issues surrounding cross-linguistic variation in "Heads, Projections, and Learnability" (Volume 1) and in "Binding, Dependencies, and Learnability" (Volume 2) are arguably the most fundamental in UG. How can principles of grammar be learned by general learning theory? What is biologically programmed in the human species in order to guarantee their learnability? What is the true linguistic representation for these areas of language knowledge? What universals exist across languages? The two volumes summarize the most critical current proposals in each area, and offer both theoretical and empirical evidence bearing on them. Research on first language acquisition and formal learnability theory is placed at the center of debates relative to linguistic theory in each area. The convergence of research across several different disciplines -- linguistics, developmental psychology, and computer science -- represented in these volumes provides a paradigm example of cognitive science.

Table of Contents

Lust, (Vol.1)Barbara; Suer, Margarita; Whitman, John; Lust, (Vol.2)Barbara; Hermon, Gabriella

Critics' Reviews

"This is perhaps the most comprehensive and intelligible presentation of current first language acquisition theory within (and extending) a Principles and Parameters approach. the quality of the 39 papers is generally extremely high, and the editing is suburb....there is much in these volumes to interest second language researchers. Issues of learnability, language-specific versus universal proceses, and continuity pervade acquisition studies whether they focus on first or second language acquisition. And for those who wish to catch up on the trends in linguistic theory-driven first language, the very accessibility of these volumes makes them worth the investment....the reader will be rewarded both by a deepened understanding of the theory itself and by some trends and conclusions in this research." — Studies in Second Language Acquisition "Since the origins of modern work in generative grammar, theory construction has adopted a framework that may be interpreted as an abstract model of acquisition, and it has been clear that research should proceed in close interaction with investigations of the actual process of language acquisition, each study informing the other. These volumes show how much progress has been made in recent years in turning this hope into a reality. They are an impressive contribution, which give a highly informative picture of the state of contemporary understanding, and should greatly stimulate and advance these interacting inquiries." — Noam Chomsky Massachusetts Institute of Technology

About VitalSource eBooks

VitalSource is a leading provider of eBooks.

  • Access your materials anywhere, at anytime.
  • Customer preferences like text size, font type, page color and more.
  • Take annotations in line as you read.

Multiple eBook Copies

This eBook is already in your shopping cart. If you would like to replace it with a different purchasing option please remove the current eBook option from your cart.

Book Preview

strong continuity hypothesis

The country you have selected will result in the following:

  • Product pricing will be adjusted to match the corresponding currency.
  • The title Perception will be removed from your cart because it is not available in this region.

U.S. flag

An official website of the United States government

The .gov means it’s official. Federal government websites often end in .gov or .mil. Before sharing sensitive information, make sure you’re on a federal government site.

The site is secure. The https:// ensures that you are connecting to the official website and that any information you provide is encrypted and transmitted securely.

  • Publications
  • Account settings

Preview improvements coming to the PMC website in October 2024. Learn More or Try it out now .

  • Advanced Search
  • Journal List
  • Front Psychiatry

Consciousness across Sleep and Wake: Discontinuity and Continuity of Memory Experiences As a Reflection of Consolidation Processes

Caroline l. horton.

1 DrEAMSLab, Psychology, Bishop Grosseteste University, Lincoln, United Kingdom

The continuity hypothesis ( 1 ) posits that there is continuity, of some form, between waking and dreaming mentation. A recent body of work has provided convincing evidence for different aspects of continuity, for instance that some salient experiences from waking life seem to feature in dreams over others, with a particular role for emotional arousal as accompanying these experiences, both during waking and while asleep. However, discontinuities have been somewhat dismissed as being either a product of activation-synthesis, an error within the consciousness binding process during sleep, a methodological anomaly, or simply as yet unexplained. This paper presents an overview of discontinuity within dreaming and waking cognition, arguing that disruptions of consciousness are as common a feature of waking cognition as of dreaming cognition, and that processes of sleep-dependent memory consolidation of autobiographical experiences can in part account for some of the discontinuities of sleeping cognition in a functional way. By drawing upon evidence of the incorporation, fragmentation, and reorganization of memories within dreams, this paper proposes a model of discontinuity whereby the fragmentation of autobiographical and episodic memories during sleep, as part of the consolidation process, render salient aspects of those memories subsequently available for retrieval in isolation from their contextual features. As such discontinuity of consciousness in sleep is functional and normal.

Continuity in Its General Form

The continuity hypothesis ( 1 ) posits that there is continuity, of some form, between waking and dreaming. A recent body of work [e.g., Ref. ( 1 – 10 )] has provided convincing evidence for the characteristics of specific aspects of continuity, for instance that some salient experiences from waking-life feature in dreams over others. Five factors have been proposed to account for the incorporation of waking-life experiences into dreams ( 11 ): the emotionality of the waking-life experience; the type of waking-life activity; personality traits; time intervals; and time of night. Emotional arousal consistently seems to accompany these experiences, both during waking (original experience) and while dreaming [for a review, see Ref. ( 10 )].

Continuity between dreaming and waking, therefore, appears to provide a framework for studying and measuring the extent of overlap, or shared variance, between different states of consciousness ( 11 ). This holds appeal in that—hypothetically—scholars could build models predicting dream content and characteristics given knowledge about specific predictor parameters, such as the emotionality of past experiences and time spent asleep. Previous attempts to conceptualize variability in dream behaviors such as dream recall ( 12 ) left 91.6% variance unexplained. As such the task at hand is ambitious. It also assumes that any as yet explained variance may be problematic, or simply, “error.” Indeed, discontinuities have been somewhat dismissed as being either a product of activation-synthesis [for instance, see Ref. ( 13 )], an error within the consciousness binding process during sleep, a methodological anomaly, or simply as yet unexplained. Furthermore, the concept of continuity remains somewhat ill-defined ( 14 ). This paper presents a conception of discontinuity within dreaming and waking cognition for the first time, arguing that disruptions of consciousness are as common a feature of waking cognition as of dreaming cognition, and that processes of sleep-dependent memory consolidation of autobiographical experiences can in part account for many of the discontinuities of sleeping cognition in a functional way. By drawing upon evidence of the incorporation, fragmentation, and reorganization of memories within dreams, this paper proposes a model of the fragmentation of autobiographical and episodic memories during sleep, which manifest as discontinuity during sleep, rendering salient aspects of those memories subsequently available for consolidation in isolation from their contextual features.

In sum the discontinuities of cognition in dreams have previously been recognized as being both typical of normal sleep mentation behavior, and possibly indicative of problematic dissociative symptoms, such as schizophrenia [e.g., Ref. ( 15 , 16 )]. This paper summarizes the elements of continuous and discontinuous processing across sleep and wake, recognizing that discontinuities in form, of cognition and of consciousness are typical and indeed functional of waking processing as well as in dreams (i.e., sleeping processing). At first glance, this may appear to be at odds with literature and evidence demonstrating that dreaming cognition, as a reflection of rapid eye movement (REM) sleep ( 13 , 17 ), is dissociative and, therefore, symptomatic of psychosis. However, this paper will conceptualize discontinuity independently from concepts of continuity and dissociation in order to clarify this standpoint.

The continuity and discontinuity of dreaming mentation has to date been explored in a handful of studies, with the latter in part being related to the experience of bizarreness. This paper provides an alternative account of such discontinuities and attempts to conceptualize dreaming cognition as being functionally discontinuous for the first time, while offering theoretical accounts of continuity and discontinuity across sleep and wake.

There has thus far been little agreement over a definition of the term, “continuity,” when it refers to the carryover of aspects of waking life into dreams and dreams into waking life ( 14 ). This paper attempts to clarity this and proposes a workable conception of continuity, with reference to the retrieval of prior experiences into consciousness at any given time.

Continuity of Consciousness

The field of sleep science well recognizes that sleep is a heterogeneous state. As distinct stages of sleep are defined by specific patterns of neural activity, measured using electroencephalogy, we assume that cognition during sleep changes also. What is less clear is how consciousness, usually measured using sleep or dream “mentation” reports, changes in line with this. This is less clear because it is difficult to access reports of conscious experience from sleep, as recall of those experiences is poor and changeable as an individual wakes from sleep. 1 Perhaps, due to this methodological challenge, there has been relatively little interest in consciousness during sleep within the field of sleep science. Dream researchers, on the other hand, use a variety of methods to capture fragments of conscious experience from sleep, including at times relying on spontaneous awakenings or the “most recent dream” method of recall and report, which likely bias findings to a sample of REM sleep dreams. Dreams sampled from REM are, indeed, typically easier to recall than dreams from other stages of sleep ( 18 ) and are also more bizarre, lengthy and emotionally intense. Comparable changes have also been documented from dreams sampled across the night, shifting from early (more coordinated) to late (more bizarre and discontinuous) ( 7 , 19 , 20 ). This seems somewhat different to the traditional view of waking conscious thought as focused, under control, and efficient. To illustrate this, Hartmann ( 21 ) depicted a model of consciousness as a dimension ranging from focused thought in wake at one end, to looser, hyperassociative cognition in REM sleep at the other, with a variety of intermediate states such as daydreaming and non-REM sleep featuring some degree of both control and bizarreness.

However, it seems vastly over-simplistic to think of waking consciousness as being homogeneous. It also seems somewhat optimistic to characterize waking thought as consistently focused and efficient. Take for example the metacognitive awareness of realizing that you have been trying to read the same paragraph of text for some time, without really having processed any of it. Or the conscious act of daydreaming: a part-focused activity perhaps with a pleasant goal but one that requires fantasy, mind-wandering and a loss of engagement with reality. Other examples combining high-level metacognitive functioning with a loss of engagement with reality include experience deja-vu, having involuntary autobiographical memories (AMs) interrupt focused thought, and meditation. During wake, we often appear not to notice events in our immediate environment (for a more dramatic example consider change blindness, in which observers often fail to notice major visual changes to a stimulus). As such, consciousness is extremely discontinuous, particularly with its focus sometimes being on the external environment and sometimes detaching from this almost completely, with the conscious awareness being directed toward internal states of reflection. Furthermore, most theories of consciousness distinguish between the more essential and automatic processes of responding to environmental needs, and the high-order cognitive processes of awareness of self in place and time [e.g., Ref. ( 22 , 23 )].

While there seems to be change in the manifestation and perhaps function of consciousness both across sleep and wake, and within each of those states, there also exists continuity. Continuity across sleep and wake to some extent is unsurprising as the same neurophysiological and cognitive system (i.e., the person) functions across these states. Across wake, dreaming and daydreaming, for example, we are also able to recall our past experiences, to demonstrate awareness of moments when we somewhat lose engagement with reality and transport our present conscious awareness to the future in the form of planning and setting goals. Thus, consciousness in part involves the activation and awareness of memory. Memories for our own personal experiences, AMs ( 24 – 26 ) may provide a framework for such continuity over time. Indeed, the AM system acknowledges that a personal life story changes over time, with memories for specific experiences being updated and constructed in accordance with long-term goals and identities ( 25 ).

One way of conceptualizing continuity then is in terms of the activation of memories across time. Indeed, a dream that is continuous with waking life should, in theory, feature real experiences, or AMs. Continuity, therefore, would be high if AMs were activated and recalled accurately and in full. Conversely discontinuity, or low continuity, would prevail if AMs were activated partially or inaccurately. The problem with this view is that very rarely are AMs recalled in full and accurately. To recall an experience fully, with many details as featured in the original experience, would be to recall an episodic memory ( 24 , 27 , 28 ). Very rarely do we recall episodes in this way. Rather, we remember part-details and at times fill in the blanks, creating a narrative that aligns well with a goal or identity ( 26 ). Furthermore, this seems characteristic of sleeping mentation as well as wake ( 8 , 29 ). As such, we can present two arguments: (i) consciousness is varied across both sleep and wake, yet (ii) in both states continuity of memory may not prevail.

Previous studies have explored the overlap, or continuity, of cognitive processing style from waking life to dreaming. Hobson et al.’s ( 13 ) activation-input-modulation (AIM) model of dreaming assumes that dreaming is illogical and lacks self-reflective awareness and directed thought, and it points to neurophysiological changes in REM sleep as the correlate for that mode of thought ( 30 ). However, empirical explorations of the continuity of cognition across sleep and wake have reflected more similarities than differences in cognition and metacognition ( 31 ), on measures of internal commentary, public self-awareness, frequency of emotion, self-reflection, and thwarted intentions. The only measure of cognition on which the two states differed were choice, event-related self-reflection and affect, with dreams being more emotional but having fewer feelings of volition, suggesting that dreaming and waking cognition are largely comparable in many respects ( 31 ). It is widely reported that the dorsolateral prefrontal cortex is relatively attenuated during REM sleep ( 32 – 34 ), which may well account for the reduced volition during REM sleep. However, we must be careful not to over-simplify these findings, recognizing that volition is still possible during sleep, as evidenced by the wealth of empirical work into the experience of lucid dreaming. Taken together, there is much evidence for comparable cognitive processing across sleep and wake. Kahan and LaBerge ( 35 ) suggest that differences between waking and dreaming cognition may be quantitative; there being more of certain cognitions in waking than dreaming and vice versa , but not qualitative, since there were incidences of the different types of cognitions sampled from both states.

Another way of accounting for the processing styles across wake and dreaming has been evidenced by Kahn and Hobson ( 36 ), who distinguished between thinking within dreams, which they argue was similar to waking thought states, and thinking about dreams, which they argued differed. Here, the authors compared cognitive functioning in dreams with that of wake, by asking participants questions about specific dream experiences. They highlighted that thinking within the dream is similar to thinking when awake even though some implausible activities and events within dreams are accepted without question (“thinking about  …”), whereas in wake we are aware of the source of events. This awareness of the origin of events as being either internal, such as a thought or a dream, or external in that it is truly perceived, is known as reality monitoring ( 37 ). Reality monitoring is known to be deficient during dreaming, when we accept surrounding circumstances without question, with the exception of experiencing lucidity, when we become aware that we are dreaming ( 36 , 38 ). Nevertheless we have further evidence that dreaming and waking cognition is largely comparable, with dreaming reflecting a sleep state in which reality monitoring is typically reduced. This gives rise to the possibility that the dreamer can process, or think about, scenarios that would not be encountered in waking life, perhaps as a rehearsal strategy of some kind [e.g., Ref. ( 39 )].

This view is reiterated by Kozmová and Wolman ( 40 ), who point out that the differences between the findings of cognitive researchers and neurophysiological researchers may be explained by the fact that while Kahan and colleagues are focused on cognition within a dream, Hobson and colleagues in theories like the AIM model of dreaming focus more on features of dreaming such as uncertainty about people and places, and incongruous imagery. Nevertheless, the specific features of dreams as compared to waking memories may reflect the cognitive processing capacities at the time of being experienced and recalled, and consequently it is difficult to separate out cognition from features. In their study, Kozmová and Wolman ( 40 ) identified thought units as featuring cognitive or metacognitive processing, such as being analytical or operational, and in doing so illustrated the complexity of cognitions available in dreaming, concluding that the content of the dream (be it bizarre or not) does not preclude the application of rational thought, much like one would in waking life, and in fact the thought processes applied to a dream situation have much in common with those applied to a situation experienced in waking life. Any differences in cognitions between sleep and wake may be exemplified by the generation of bizarre scenarios, than how the mind approaches those scenarios, in line with Kahn and Hobson ( 36 ) views.

Kahn and Hobson ( 36 ) further account for the lack of reality monitoring during REM sleep dreaming by the reduced activity of the dorsolateral prefrontal cortex and precuneus, as well as the functional disconnect between these structures ( 32 – 34 ), meaning the brain cannot distinguish between who, where and what we are within a given context. This can account for not only the poor reality monitoring during dreaming, but also the typically disorganized or bizarre string of memory sources that comprise our dreams ( 41 ). As such, the way in which our cognition operates across different states may be largely continuous, but there seems to exist differences in the organization of our memories between sleep and wake. Given the complexities of the characteristics of continuity between sleep and wake and even across sleep ( 7 , 19 ), it is unsurprising that efforts to account for continuity have thus far been limited.

What Might be the Function of Continuity?

If we proceed with our definition of consciousness as a holistic experience of the present, brief past, long-term past ( via memory retrieval) and the future (goal directed), we may assume that the ability to recall prior experiences, i.e., for continuity to function, would allow focus to be maintained in reaching future goals. In addition, as with the function of any memory system, the ability to recall prior experiences is the consequence of successful learning and allows those experiences to shape our interaction with the world in light of them. The activation of prior experience in a truly continuous manner would mean that we need to access all aspects of that prior experience. As we have seen, prior experiences are rarely recalled episodically, and so perhaps only salient aspects are particularly accessible at any one time, depending on need. Similarly, during sleep prior experiences may be activated either in full [rarely; see Ref. ( 8 )] or in part and the activation of those salient aspects may strengthen them for future accessibility ( 42 ).

Ordered, controlled, and focused consciousness is also deemed to be a marker of psychological health, with authors such as Llewellyn ( 16 ) suggesting that a less structured or continuous consciousness may reflect elements of psychosis. Psychosis is characterized by disorganized cognition, seemingly leaping from one thought to another. The breakdown of holistic conscious experience is also reflected in dissociation; detachment from either the perception of reality or separation of the experience of the past. The essential feature of Dissociative Disorders is defined as “a disruption of and/or discontinuity in the normal integration of consciousness, memory, identity, emotion, perception, body representation, motor control, and behaviour” ( 43 ). The DSM-5 positions the dissociative disorders next to the trauma- and stressor-related disorders, to reflect the close relationship between these diagnostic categories ( 44 ). Dissociation can be exacerbated by sleep loss ( 45 ) and sleep disturbances are symptomatic (or perhaps even causal) of virtually all mental disorders as listed in the DSM-5 ( 43 ). This implies that sleep serves an integrative function for the mind and body. Indeed, in cognitive terms during sleep, we activate and re-activate experiences from the past (in particular the recent past), giving rise to the experience of dreams when we can recall the mental activation upon awakening. However, as we have already seen, when we explore the characteristics of dreams it is evident that consciousness is rarely continuous [e.g., Ref. ( 7 , 18 )]. As such while sleep may help to maintain order of consciousness and overall mental health, it apparently does not reflect continuity of it. 2

What is Discontinuity?

If continuity refers to the ability to retrieve the past, and the future where relevant (goals), in the context of present awareness (consciousness), then it would follow logically that discontinuity is the opposite of this, whereby discontinuity would be the inability to retrieve the past or future in the context of the present. Also, if continuity involves recalling past experiences holistically, discontinuity could refer to recalling them in a fragmentary manner. As we have noted, such discontinuity seems characteristic of both waking and sleeping cognition.

However, discontinuity may not always be conceptualized in opposition to continuity. Both Hobson and Schredl ( 14 ) and Malinowski and Horton ( 5 , 6 ) acknowledge that the continuity-discontinuity spectrum may be a gradient, rather than discrete entities. For example, recalling a dream (continuity of dreaming memories to wake) may involve accessing a number of features of the original experience, but with some added appraisal of the experience and with some features being omitted from memory. This appears both continuous and discontinuous at the same time. Similarly dreaming of an upcoming social event (from waking life) may seem largely continuous in the manner of reflecting concerns, characters involved and the general setting, but could be discontinuous in that the actual future event could never happen. Here, then dream–wake (or wake–dream) continuity would perhaps rarely be clearly either continuous or discontinuous, but comprising features of both.

This presents a challenge with conceptualizing continuity and discontinuity in operational terms. Future work should aim to characterize dream–wake continuity in specific ways, noting trends for specific memory features to be either largely continuous or discontinuous. 3 This may help to alleviate concerns with discontinuity as being merely unexplained variance in models of continuity that aim to predict dreaming behavior.

As we have noted, continuity can take many forms. Discontinuity could present as disjointed cognition, with absences or lapses in attention (i.e., consciousness being interrupted). Alternatively discontinuity could present, in extreme cases, as dissociation in waking, or bizarreness in dreams (consciousness during sleep). REM dreams are typically bizarre ( 48 , 49 ), featuring sudden changes and eliciting feelings of strangeness, curiosity or mystique upon awakening. As we have seen, dreams very rarely feature memories from waking life in a truly episodic form ( 8 , 29 ) and so are, by definition, discontinuous. Indeed, it seems likely that the only instances in which memories are replayed in their precise manner as they were originally experiences, is when they are so emotionally intense and negatively valenced that they were traumatic to the individual ( 50 ). In sum, full continuity here may reflect a maladapted system, while discontinuity is the norm.

Indeed several fields of study indicate the central role of the emotionality of a (waking) experience as being important for its subsequent recallability ( 51 , 52 ), consolidation [e.g., Ref. ( 53 , 54 )]; and, perhaps relatedly, its likelihood of being dreamed about [( 55 , 56 ); see also Ref. ( 10 ) for a review]. Furthermore, some studies have implied that there exists a relationship between continuity and emotional intensity, such that the more intensely emotional the experience, the more highly continuous it is, especially if it is traumatic in nature [e.g. Ref. ( 57 ), see also ( 58 )]. A somewhat emotional experience will likely be dreamed about, but in a less continuous manner [e.g., see Ref. ( 7 , 19 , 55 )]. An experience low in emotional intensity may be unlikely to require processing or be dreamed about ( 55 ). Thus, there may be just cause to further explore relationships between continuity and emotionality in dream studies. Indeed, in order to explore discontinuities across sleep and wake, Kunzendorf et al. ( 59 ) reported that dreams were more bizarre, more “dream-like,” and more emotional than daydreams. Hartmann et al. ( 60 ) found that the contextualizing images in dreams were more emotionally intense than those in daydreams, and also that dreams had mostly fear/terror and helplessness/vulnerability as their contextualizing emotion, whereas daydreams had no particularly dominant emotions. Thus, consciousness during sleep appears to be more bizarre and emotional than daydreams, although emotionality and bizarreness (perhaps representing discontinuity) is related across all states. It is also interesting to note that daydreams generated under the influence of extreme emotional intensity are more “dream-like” and more symbolic than any other kind of daydream ( 61 ). This again illustrates that the content of dreams may be different to waking thought, but, as above, the cognitions about that content may be more similar.

An interesting caveat to the generalization about dreams versus daydreams comes from Kunzendorf et al. ( 59 ) who found that participants with “thin boundaries,” i.e., people who blur the lines between various aspects of life (including waking and dreaming) more than those with “thick boundaries” who see things in more clear-cut, black-and-white terms, had daydreams that were equally as bizarre as nocturnal dreams, reinforcing the idea that there may exist strong individual differences between people who experience continuity and those who do not. The assumptions within this paper on the whole refer to patterns of general cognitive activity irrespective of any such trait effects. However, both the fields of dream science and psychopathology indicate that there exist differences between individuals in the extent to which they may experience continuity or not. For instance, some individuals are more susceptible to nightmares than others, which often feature more episodic incorporations of waking-life episodes ( 57 ). Furthermore and not unrelatedly, some individuals are more vulnerable to experiencing dissociation than others. This raises questions concerning the extent to which continuity and discontinuity may be “normal” in terms of being psychologically healthy. As stated earlier, continuity may reflect maladaptive processing. However, severe discontinuity, as in the case of experiencing dissociation, reflects a disorganized and interrupted sense of reality and as such is clearly maladaptive also. Thus, part of the role of characterizing the extent and frequency of experiencing discontinuity should help to address the issue of, “ how much discontinuity is normal ?”

A Possible Function of Discontinuity?

If discontinuity is the norm, rather than indicating a disordered system as previous literature has implied, it may have a function. A number of theories of dreaming and of consciousness have attempted to account for discontinuity in the past, and a brief review of these will follow.

Hobson et al.’s ( 13 ) AIM model of dreaming focuses on dreaming occurring during REM, which has not been empirically supported as dreams can be sampled easily from non-REM sleep and REM does not always lead to dream recall. Nevertheless, the model proposes that with correct activation and cognitive input, dreaming will result. A dream report is deemed to be the result of a “synthesis” of activations, which taken together are neither meaningful nor functional. As such according to this model, discontinuity is the norm during REM sleep and is taken to reflect the lack of order and purpose of the epiphenomena of dreams.

Somewhat relatedly, models, such as Schredl’s ( 1 , 62 ), attempt to characterize the likelihood of recalling dreams and even dreaming of specific material. However, unexplained variance remains so high (91.6%) that these models have many more factors yet to uncover in the pursuit of understanding the nature of dreaming. The as yet unexplained variance may reflect discontinuity, which is difficult to conceptualize let alone predict using existing methods and the continuity hypothesis as a theoretical underpinning ( 1 ), though of course this does not imply necessarily that such discontinuity is unimportant. Rather just that dream scientists have much work to do!

An alternative set of views concerns the style of cognitive processing that seems typical of REM, or late-night, sleep. As Hartmann ( 21 ) suggested, but did not test empirically, REM sleep cognition may be hyperassociative , in that the links from one activated thought to another are more tenuous than in waking. Indeed, this is one way of thinking about discontinuity as illogical or surprising links from one processing sequence to another. In cognitive psychology, this would represent a weak semantic association rather than a strong one, with the latter typically reflecting focused thought and goal-oriented processing. Hartmann, however, did not speculate as to what the function of such hyperassociativity may have been, although he was a psychoanalyst and so believed that dreams had a language that could be uncovered therapeutically. Implicit in that view was the notion that manifest dream content was merely only part of a dream’s make-up, meaning that some degree of interpretation was required on Hartmann’s part. Such a view is largely at odds with more contemporary approaches to dream science, in which memory sources of dreams are deemed to reflect more explicitly the activation of waking-life experiences that may be processed during sleep, perhaps as part of a memory consolidation process ( 2 – 4 ).

An alternative body of work from both the sleep and dreaming fields explore the creativity associated with REM sleep (in particular). The hyperassociative processing style, or “loose” connections in Hartmann ( 21 ) terms, provide a mental space for creativity and novel solutions to become conscious. A great deal of evidence shows the relationships between REM sleep and creativity [e.g., Ref. ( 63 )]. However, evidence also demonstrates the relationships between creativity and dissociation, with the latter in part being increased with sleep disturbances, as we have already seen ( 64 ), reinforcing the complex relationships between psychopathology and creativity.

Nevertheless the relationship between REM sleep and novel ideas has been shown in a number of empirical investigations exploring not only creativity but also problem solving and insight. Thus there seems to be something about the activity in REM sleep, or at least following several iterations of preceding non-REM sleep cycles, that promotes the formation of new concepts and ideas. Merely re-activating previous experiences episodically, i.e., continuity, would not logically facilitate such novelty. Rather, then discontinuity may involve the reactivation of some elements of previous experiences, but perhaps in parallel with additional experiences or in quick succession to dissimilar, or weakly associated, experiences—we do not yet know whether such hypothesized hyperassociativity operates in parallel or sequentially. We may assume that discontinuity involves the activation of memory fragments taken from a number of memory sources that are bound together into a conscious uniform experience, as dream images seem to comprise such condensed imagery ( 4 , 65 ). If this is the case discontinuity, comprising hyperassociative processing, could be evidenced by the analysis of the memory sources of dreams. For example, one dream image featuring several identified memory sources, such as a character that we recognize from recent waking life, a familiar place in which the dream is set, the content of a conversation in the dream, as well as additional specific features, such as objects, people, or activities, can each be rated in terms of the dreamer’s familiarity with them, their age or time since being experienced (if at all), as well as more general features such as counting the number of memory sources in dream images across the night or sampled from different stages of sleep. Llewellyn ( 65 ) illustrates this in detail with her “quicksand dream,” showcasing how various different elements of waking life had been recombined and synthesized into a single, composite dream event. Llewellyn postulated that this process in dreaming operates to create episodic “landmark junctions” at a neural level. However, such discontinuity could have many purposes, not least to decontextualize each of the composite memory sources, rendering each individual contribution memorable in its own right. Such studies of discontinuity could inform much about the activation of autobiographical experiences across different states of consciousness.

To this end, discontinuity seems to allow novel insights and creative possibilities. However, very few individuals wake from a dream experiencing a sudden moment of clarity or enhanced understanding into a problem. As such, we cannot assume that discontinuity functions to make revelations conscious. Rather, discontinuity in sleep, and likely in wake also though perhaps to a lesser extent, may reflect offline processing that maintains the organization and consolidation of experiences within a neurocognitive system that is constantly being updated. During wake the human brain perceives a great wealth of novel information that requires processing and integration with existing structures. Much of this information will be superfluous to requirements and processing will cease very shortly after sensation. However, some will be salient enough to require consolidation into long-term memory networks, to be accessible for future use and to require prior knowledge to be updated. Such consolidation and re-consolidation likely occur constantly, though sleep seems to be the time when much of this consolidation occurs ( 66 – 70 ). Furthermore, sleep appears to afford opportunities for the reorganization of memory networks ( 22 , 65 , 71 , 72 ) and thus the integration of newer experiences into pre-existing cortical structures ( 70 , 73 – 75 ).

In order to evidence the idea that discontinuity engenders consolidation and integration of novel experiences with more established memory networks, we should be able to identify a change in the organization and representation of memory sources over time, as they become increasingly integrated. This should be mapped on to changes in the continuity, or order, of the conscious manifestation of that experience. A handful of dream studies have been able to map the activation of a specific memory source over time, although unfortunately these studies are varied in their methodological approach. Some short-term approaches have looked at the organization of memory representations across the night, with early-night sleep being rich in non-REM, slow-wave sleep, and later night sleep being richer in REM ( 7 ). More recently, we ( 19 ) have also demonstrated changes in the continuity of memory representations across the night, with dreams being sampled from later night sleep being more bizarre yet more integrated with older memory sources. Thus, to evidence a change in the organization and representation of a memory over time we may expect to see a memory source, appearing in a dream in a decreasingly literal manner as it is consolidated. Some postulate that the representation may become increasingly metaphorical ( 10 ), although this is difficult to evidence empirically. Hopefully in the future sleep study technology will afford the more accurate monitoring of this with neural mapping of the activation of the original memory engram along with a representation of the extent to which it has been integrated into long-term cortical structures. At present, we can rely on subjective dream reports and an analysis of their memory sources.

Long-term approaches have typically explored emotionally charged experiences being incorporated into dreams and have documented corresponding changes in the characteristics of those emotional memory representations over time [e.g., Ref. ( 62 , 66 , 76 )]. Convincing evidence of relations between emotional waking-life experiences and dreams comes from studies with victims of trauma [for reviews, see Ref. ( 10 , 77 )]. For example, individuals with direct military experience of war have direct, unambiguous, and sometimes apparently veridical dream incorporations of their experiences; civilians, on the other hand, have “indirect” or “symbolic” incorporations ( 78 ). Thus, it may be that the more traumatic the experience, the more direct the incorporation of the experience into dreaming, as is also the case with posttraumatic stress disorder symptomatology. Cartwright ( 76 ) also reports of her studies with divorcees, who dreamed of their divorce process over time, and the shift from dream reports being more accurately reflective of current concerns and experiences, to being more symbolically represented as the divorce process was appraised and comes to terms with by the dreamer.

Indeed, these emotional experiences may be particularly pertinent. Several theories of sleep-dependent memory processing emphasize the role of emotion, either in identifying a particular aspect of a memory to be processed ( 79 ) or in signaling heightened activity during the consolidation process in sleep ( 80 ). Stickgold and Walker ( 42 ) presented a “triage” model of sleep-dependent memory consolidation, whereby salient aspects of an experience are tagged as requiring processing during sleep. Emotional intensity likely acts as this triage indicator. Concurrently, a growing number of studies now indicate that emotional waking-life experiences are more likely to feature in dreams compared to neutral experiences ( 9 , 19 , 55 , 62 , 81 ).

The consequence here is that experiences that have been well integrated into a memory network and that have been processed emotionally, would not manifest in dreams in a manner that largely reflects their original experience in waking life. In this way, the more discontinuous the representation of the experience, the more integrated and perhaps the more accepted (emotionally) it has become. Thus discontinuity can reflect a healthy cognitive system, rather than being a sign of psychopathology, as has been implied in previous accounts of consciousness. This may appear counterintuitive but suggests that discontinuity is a functional end-point of a cognitive process of integration and consolidation.

The Characteristics of Memory Experience Across Sleep and Wake

Horton and Malinowski ( 4 ) proposed a model of AM consolidation in sleep, whereby memories for waking experiences can appear in dreams in largely fragmentary forms and as such differ from conventional manifestations of episodic memory. AMs in dreams can be sampled from non-REM as well as REM periods, which contain fewer episodic references and become more bizarre across the night ( 41 , 82 ). Salient fragmented memory features are activated in sleep and rebound with fragments not necessarily emerging from the same memory, thus de-contextualizing those memories and manifesting as experiences that differ from waking conceptions. The constructive nature of autobiographical recall further encourages synthesis of these hyperassociated images into an episode via recalling and reporting dreams. This model of sleep-dependent memory consolidation accounts for the discontinuity within REM sleep mentation, and perhaps in elements of non-REM sleep reports and in aspects of waking also, as the fragmentary activation of specific memories being coupled with other memory fragments, giving rise to a new image, illustrates discontinuity clearly. Here, we can synthesize the characteristics of discontinuity with the activation of fragments of memory sources in sleep.

In sum the discontinuities of cognition in dreams have been recognized as being both typical of normal sleep mentation behavior, and possibly indicative of problematic dissociative symptoms, such as schizophrenia [e.g., Ref. ( 16 )]. In this paper, I summarized the elements of continuous and discontinuous processing across sleep and wake, recognizing that discontinuities in form, of cognition and of consciousness are typical and indeed functional of waking processing as well as in dreams (i.e., sleeping processing).

The behavioral outcome, i.e., what is consolidated and/or consciously experienced is, more often than not, unclear upon awakening and usually later following dreaming. As the dream memory fades so quickly and it is only in the case of the few avid dreamers who may engage in consideration of their dream experiences that they claim to have an understanding of what their dream “meant” or represented, we cannot assume that a clear purpose of dreaming is to have conscious clarity or insight following the dream experience. The discontinuity of a dream and the associated feelings of bizarreness may contribute to this perception that dreams are perhaps not there to be understood as such. Nevertheless, discontinuity within and across dreaming and waking may still be functional if the activated memory fragments in sleep, manifesting in dream reports, remain accessible over and above other, non-incorporated memories at a later date.

Discontinuity as we have conceptualized it here is the fragmentation of experiences as we tend to perceive them in the present. That may refer to dreaming of an event from waking life in a very different way to the original experience, or it may refer to simply recalling an experience in a different way to its original occurrence. Thus, discontinuity could refer to the change of a memory representation over time, whether that be in a dream or when recalled at a later time in waking.

In this paper, I have argued that discontinuity is typical of both waking as well as sleeping cognition as in waking it is a normal characteristic of autobiographical remembering. During sleep, as evidenced from dream reports from across the night, experiences from our waking lives are particularly discontinuous as specific constituent features of autobiographical experiences are selected for processing. However, under the backdrop of continuous consciousness, whereby the stream of thoughts, images, and cognitions are sewn together into a coherent narrative, individual memory fragments are bound together to create a new “episode,” which is certainly discontinuous from waking life as it may be implausible, incongruous or impossible (e.g., dreaming of talking to someone who has recently passed away).

The consequence of this is that the dream product may provide insight via consideration of novel experiences, but may not have been composed in a deliberately metaphorical or symbolic manner.

This leads us to present some testable hypotheses for future work in this field, linking sleep-dependent memory consolidation, the characteristics of dreams (of prior waking experiences) and the recallability of AMs over time. Experiences from waking life (AMs) that have been dreamed about in a discontinuous manner would likely be less emotionally intense than those that are continuous. Also the memory fragments that were rebound with another memory (source) during dreaming should lead to enhanced recallability of both the original source of the memory fragment as well as the memory source that appeared in the dream, relative to memories and fragments that had not been dreamed about, due to all these aspects having been activated during sleep. A recent study ( 83 ), documented the incorporation of recent autobiographical experiences into dreams that had been documented in a 14-day diary. Memory for those original experiences was tested via recall and recognition. Those experiences that had been incorporated into dreams were better recalled and recognized later. While this may seem unsurprising as the act of reporting a dream could be seen to rehearse those original experiences, the representation of the experience in the dream was often far different to the original episode. This provides a starting framework for exploring links between (dis)continuity and memory consolidation of declarative experiences.

These predictions present exciting opportunities for the collaboration of dream and sleep scientists with memory consolidation scholars, to explore the nature of sleeping mentation as a reflection of the cognitive processes of memory reorganization over time. They also should not detract from the contributions and efforts of continuity theorists, who may, in part, aim to predict dream behaviors given certain parameters. Rather, discontinuity needs to be characterized in relation to continuity to help us to appreciate further the wonderful changing state of consciousness, what it might tell us about the activation of memories during sleep; something that neuroimaging methods are not yet able to do in a detailed manner.

Furthermore, scholars should continue attempting to identify whether patterns of discontinuity and continuity are consistent or varied across individuals. For instance, some existing work has identified benefits of a labile sleep–wake pattern in terms of the number of cycles through sleep stages upon knowledge awareness tasks ( 84 , 85 ) and recent work has identified that lucid dreaming training benefits performance in field independence tasks ( 86 ). As such identifying patterns of cognitive functioning and discontinuity of consciousness that seem optimal for both mental health and memory consolidation could pave the way for similar training or intervention studies, if patterns of discontinuity may be changeable across individuals.

Author Contributions

As sole author CH prepared the manuscript and ideas therein in full.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

1 It is assumed, here, that dreaming is considered to be a reflection of conscious activity during sleep and that, as such, it is not different to sleeping cognition or even reflective of specific stages of sleep. Indeed, several studies demonstrate that dreams can be successfully sampled from sleep onset, non-REM as well as REM stages under appropriate systematic conditions [e.g., Ref. ( 18 )]. As such, the definition of dreaming preferred here is a report of a mental activity experienced during sleep .

2 It is necessary to mention here that in these discussions that acknowledge the changeable nature of consciousness, we are referring to continuous and discontinuous functioning as a state, rather than a trait. Explorations of dissociative tendency typically refer to individuals who experience discontinuity more readily and frequently than others. However, my own work has noted that, despite these individual differences, there exists great variability within people’s dreaming tendencies. As such experiencing a particularly discontinuous dream, for instance, should not necessarily indicate problematic cognition or experiences, especially of a clinical nature. Furthermore, therapists and clinicians should always be wary of relying on dreams as part of any clinical diagnosis, unless sampled reliably and systematically. Great biases exist in dream reports, with some individuals much more likely to recall dreams generally than others [e.g., see Ref. ( 46 )]. As such, encouraging anyone to try to recall a dream could over-rely on creative or imaginative processes, rather than capturing a valid dream memory. Similarly, some individuals seemingly very ready to report a dream could be particularly susceptible to creating the report without apparent effort, falsely believing that their report is true ( 47 ).

3 One present project within my own lab is exploring this, by creating a dream memory database and charting the likelihood of individual memory fragments (objects, characters, place, sounds, etc.) as being continuous or discontinuous.



If you use this paper in research, please use the following citation, as this on-line version is simply a reprint of the original article:
Domhoff, G. W. (2017). The invasion of the concept snatchers: The origins, distortions, and future of the continuity hypothesis. , , 14-39.

This article explains the origins and development of the continuity hypothesis in work by cognitively oriented dream researchers. Using blind quantitative analyses of lengthy dream series from several individuals, in conjunction with inferences presented to the individual dreamers to corroborate or reject, these researchers discovered that the same conceptions and personal concerns that animate waking thought are very often enacted in dreams. Other types of studies later supported this finding. The article argues that the cognitive origins and definition of the continuity hypothesis have been distorted by those dream researchers who mistakenly claim that the concept is focused on dreaming as an incorporation of everyday experiences. A review of the literature on experiential and experimental influences on dreams, which includes studies of day residues, the experimental manipulation of presleep events, the incorporation of during-sleep stimuli, laboratory references in laboratory-collected dreams, and the influence of routine daily events, reveals that none of them is very influential and most are trivial. The article concludes that those who study experiential factors should adopt a phrase such as "incorporation hypothesis" to avoid confusion in the literature and make clear that the continuity hypothesis is a central one in an emerging neurocognitive theory of dreams. The intensity of personal concerns and interests, not the events of the day, shape central aspects of dream content. In particular, the frequency of characters or activities reveals the intensity of various concerns, and these concerns can be discovered for individuals through comparisons with normative findings.

The continuity hypothesis put forth in the early 1970s by pioneer dream researcher and cognitive theorist Calvin S. Hall and his coauthor (Bell & Hall, 1971) is widely known and discussed by dream researchers. In its fully developed form, as one key concept in a cognitive theory that has become a neurocognitive theory, the continuity hypothesis states that a large majority of dreams (the exact percentage has not yet been established) express the same conceptions (e.g., of oneself, of specific relatives and friends) and personal concerns (e.g., relationships, avocations) that animate waking thought (Domhoff, 1996, pp. 5, 153; 2001). Building on the working hypothesis that the frequency with which a character, type of social interaction, or activity appears in a series of dreams reveals the intensity of a concern, predictions can be made about the conceptions and personal concerns that are most important for both groups and individuals (Hall & Van de Castle, 1966, pp. 13-14).

More specifically, based on blind quantitative content analyses of a set or series of dream reports, this approach leads to the hypothesis that statistically significant differences between two sets of dream reports, or between an individual dreams series and normative baselines, will relate to the psychologically unique aspects of the dreamers' waking thoughts. Thus, the theory, based on a wealth of past findings, presents a clear statement of what is the most important influence on the frequency of specific types of content in dreams: the intensity of personal concerns.

However, despite the clear meaning that had been established for this concept within the context of a cognitive theory of dreaming by the late 1990s at the latest, it has been repeatedly misstated since that time by more recent dream researchers. The original misguided restatement mistakenly claimed that the essence of the concept is that dreams "reflect" waking-life experiences, with an emphasis on the "incorporation rate" of various types of experiences (Schredl, 2003, p. 26). This formulation is the opposite of dreams as being to a large extent the expression ( enactment and dramatization are often used as synonyms) of conceptions and concerns, some of which go back years and decades for many individual dreamers. Despite strong criticisms of this experientialist distortion of the cognitively oriented continuity hypothesis (Bulkeley, 2011, 2012; Domhoff, 2003, 2010b; Domhoff, Meyer-Gomes, & Schredl, 2006), this altered version has been uncritically adopted by many dream researchers without any mention of the original meaning of the concept or of the criticisms of the experiential incorporation version (e.g., King & DeCicco, 2009; Malinowski & Horton, 2011, 2014; Sándor, Szakadát, & Bódizs, 2016; Selterman, Apetroaia, Riela, & Aron, 2014). The problem also has been compounded in a follow-up statement defending and extending the original mistaken article (Schredl, 2012).

The mistaken redefinition of the continuity hypothesis has been translated into a strong indictment by dream researchers who see the continuity hypothesis as a "competitor" to their "threat simulation" and "social simulation" theories, both of which claim that dreams are rehearsals that are useful for dealing with future waking events (see Revonsuo, 2000; Revonsuo, Tuominen, & Valli, 2015, pp. 1, 11, 19, 24, for repeated statements that the continuity hypothesis is in competition with their views). Focusing primarily on the experiential distortion of the continuity hypothesis, they claim that the concept is "too vague and general as a theoretical explanation for the details of dream content," does not "predict in any detail how and why the causal relationship between waking and dreaming works," does not "specify in any detail what counts as a 'continuity' and what would count as a 'discontinuity,'" and "takes almost any similarity between waking life and dream life as a confirmation of the continuity hypothesis" (Revonsuo et al., 2015, p. 10).

In fact, these claims are false. The continuity hypothesis was not presented as a "theoretical explanation for the details of dream content" but as an empirical discovery that has been replicated numerous times, a discovery that can be explained by the idea that most dreams enact and dramatize the same conceptions, personal concerns, and personal interests that animate waking thought. (The word personal is usually connected with the mention of a "concern" or "interest" in this article because the theorists criticized in his article have stretched the original meaning of the term concern to include everyday concerns and passing daily interests.) The original version of the cognitive theory of dreams stated that dreams are the "embodiment of thoughts," and the more recent neurocognitive version states that dreams are embodied simulations that very frequently enact conceptions and personal concerns (Domhoff, 2011b, 2015, in press, Chapters 2-3; Hall, 1953, pp. 273-274). More specifically, perhaps as many as 70% of dreams may be embodied simulations of conceptions and personal concerns (Domhoff, in press, Chapter 2; Domhoff et al., 2006, Table 3, p. 276).

Because of the various misunderstandings and critiques of the continuity hypothesis, it is the purpose of this article to fully explain the origins and evolution of the continuity hypothesis as a key concept in a cognitive, and subsequently neurocognitive, theory of dreams (Domhoff, 1996, pp. 209-212; 2001, 2003, 2011b, in press). The article shows that the concept expresses a major disagreement with the predominant theorists of the clinical era of dream research, who stressed the discontinuities between dreaming and waking thought (Freud, 1900; Fromm, 1951; Jung, 1974). It explains that the concept had its origins in studies of several individual dream series, not in studies based on 2-week dream diaries and questionnaires, which are frequently used by its critics.

Although experimentally oriented skeptics sometimes claim that lengthy dream journals are selective samples that may reflect only the most memorable dreams the person recalls, as in the case of one anonymous reviewer of this article, they overlook the fact that several of these series contain three or more entries per week, which is in the range of the typical rate of dream recall (e.g., Beaulieu-Prévost & Zadra, 2005b; Beaulieu-Prévost & Zadra, 2015; Blagrove & Akehurst, 2000; Schredl, 2008). One of these series, with 2,022 dream reports over a 3-year period, often includes two or more dreams a night, for an average of 13 dream reports per week, far beyond the usual rate in most questionnaire and 2-week diary studies This series, which can be found on DreamBank.net under the pseudonym "Kenneth," leads to the same results that have been found in other studies (Domhoff, in press, Chapter 3; Domhoff & Schneider, 2008, p. 1243).

As noted at the outset, the use of blind quantitative analyses of lengthy dream series makes it possible to develop specific inferences about the dreamers' waking conceptions and personal concerns. These inferences then can be verified or rejected with extant biographical information or direct responses from the dreamers themselves. Because of mistaken inferences in some of the earliest studies making use of the concept, which are examined in the next section, the continuity hypothesis was further refined. It was then supported in later studies of longer dream series that included more detailed analyses and obtained more detailed responses to the inferences from the dreamers, along with testimony from friends of the dreamer in one instance (Bulkeley, 2012, 2014; Bulkeley & Domhoff, 2010; Domhoff, 2003, Chapter 5; 2015; in press, Chapters 3-4).

This defense of the established cognitive meaning of the continuity hypothesis is necessary because the broader definition of the concept downplays its cognitive meaning, opens the door to very loose uses of the term "continuity" by new dream researchers, and creates confusion for all dream researchers. The concluding section of the article suggests that those who include daily events, daily concerns, or episodic daily interests within the purview of their interest in continuity should use a term such as experiential orientation hypothesis , incorporation hypothesis , experiential incorporation hypothesis , or some equivalent term. They should do so because the continuity hypothesis has become an important ingredient in a cognitive tradition that envisions dreaming, along with mind-wandering and daydreaming, as a form of spontaneous, stimulus-independent thought, a tradition that accords little if any weight to everyday daytime experiences (e.g., Antrobus, Singer, Goldstein, & Fortgang, 1970; Domhoff, in press; Foulkes, 1985; Fox, Nijeboer, Solomonova, Domhoff, & Christoff, 2013).

The Origins and Later Refinement of the Continuity Hypothesis

To appreciate the importance of the continuity hypothesis, it is necessary to explain the empirical and theoretical context within which it arose as well as to report the refinements that were made to it, which are seldom or never discussed by those who have altered the meaning of the concept. Such a discussion makes it possible to show how the continuity hypothesis played a key role in the expansion of the original version of Hall's (1953) cognitive theory of dreams into the present-day idea that dreams are embodied simulations that dramatize conceptions and personal concerns (Domhoff, 1996, pp. 209-212; 2007, 2015). In the first statement of his cognitive theory of dreams, as noted in the introduction, Hall (1953, pp. 273-274) claimed that dreams are "the embodiment of thoughts" and then added that thoughts are based on "conceptions," which he explained as follows: "Thinking is a process of conceiving. The end-product of this process is a conception (idea). A conception is an item of knowledge, a formulation of experience that has meaning for a person" (Hall, 1953, p. 274).

Although the cognitive theory of dreams was first stated in 1953, the continuity hypothesis was only developed many years later in a context in which studies attempting to test psychodynamic ideas about dreams through the use of projective or paper-and-pencil measures of personality had led to meager findings. Most of these disappointing results, many of which were reported by Hall's dissertation students at Case Western University in the late 1940s and early 1950s, are summarized in a chapter in a volume on Progress in Clinical Psychology (Hall, 1956). The list of failed or inconclusive studies was updated 40 years later, although there were few or no studies undertaken after 1980 (Domhoff, 1996, pp. 154-156).

In the mid-1960s, in a new introduction to the second edition of his popular book, The Meaning of Dreams , Hall (1953/1966) further reported that he had been very wrong in his inferences in a recent study of the personalities and leadership qualities of 2 of 17 mountain climbers who wrote down their dreams for several weeks as one part of a larger study of the 1963 American Mount Everest Expedition. Although his assessments of most of the men were consistent with those of the psychologists who studied their waking behavior, the two men he thought were the most popular, the most psychologically mature, and the most effective leaders turned out to be "the least liked, the most immature, and had no leadership or morale building assets whatsoever" (Hall, 1953/1966, p. xx). He called it a "sobering experience" to discover "the enormity of the misjudgments that can be made in assessing a person's waking behavior [italics added] from his dreams" (Hall, 1953/1966, p. xx).

Thus, despite Hall's (1954; Hall & Nordby, 1973) admiration for both Freud (1900) and Jung (1963, 1974), and his use of some of their ideas, the meager or negative findings with the standard personality assessments used in psychological research, along with his own mistakes, caused him to amend his blend of cognitive and psychodynamic theory in an even more cognitive direction. However, it was not until he began to study dream series from adults about whom he could obtain autobiographical or biographical information, or who were available to respond to the inferences about current conceptions and personal concerns (based on blind analyses of their dream series), that he made any progress in understanding the specifics of the relationship between dreaming and waking thought and to conceptualize this relationship in terms of "continuity." Although dream series were first used by the early Freudian Wilhelm Stekel (Hall, 1953/1966, p. 236) and Carl Jung (1963, 1968, 1974), their use was novel in terms of empirical dream research based on quantitative content analysis.

The first published scholarly statement related to Hall's gradual development of the continuity hypothesis appeared in a book coauthored with Richard Lind on the Dreams, Life, and Literature of Franz Kafka, which was based on a content analysis of the 37 dreams found in the Kafka diaries that had been published as of the 1960s (Hall & Lind, 1970). After making various predictions about Kakfa's waking conceptions and personal concerns, which derived from a comparison of the content findings for Kafka with the male norms in Hall and Van de Castle's (1966) comprehensive quantitative coding system, Hall and Lind (1970) then turned to a careful reading of Kafka's diaries and letters, which they had purposely ignored up to this point, as well as to a reading of biographies and remembrances of Kafka.

The final chapter, entitled "Realizations," begins by noting that "modern dream theories," for all their differences, emphasize that dreams are "discontinuous with waking life" (Hall & Lind, 1970, p. 89). In other words, Hall thought that Freud, Jung, and most of the neo-Freudians overemphasized the discontinuities between waking thought and dreams in their theorizing. Freud (1900, 1901) did so through the idea that adult dreams are heavily disguised and opaque to the waking mind because they express repressed sexual and aggressive desires that have to be disguised by "the dream-work." This reworking of the repressed wishes by the four cognitive processes that comprise the dream-work makes it necessary for a Freudian-trained expert to find the meaning of any given dream, usually through obtaining free associations to each element of the dream and being alert for what are now called figurative meanings (Gibbs, 1994; Lakoff, 1987).

As for Jung (e.g., 1963, 1974; Mattoon, 1978), he claimed that important dreams were if anything the opposite of waking thoughts because they compensated for the underdeveloped aspects of the person's psyche in very arcane ways (as revealed via symbolism). This theory made expert knowledge about mythology, religious history, and general metaphoric meanings necessary for developing an understanding of dreams. Finally, neo-Freudians, through their emphasis on the alleged metaphoric nature of dreaming, also found it necessary to draw upon myths, fairy tales, and metaphors to understand the underlying meaning of dreams (Fromm, 1951). (There were a few minor dissident neo-Freudians who dissented from the emphasis on discontinuity, but their claims for continuity were based on clinical case studies and had no lasting impact [e.g., French & Fromm, 1964]). Contrary to the well-known clinical theorists who emphasized discontinuity, who far and away predominated for the first 6 decades of the 20th century, Hall and Lind (1970) put their emphasis on the following statement: "This study of Kafka's dreams in relation to his life indicates that dreams are more likely to be continuous with waking life" (Hall & Lind, 1970, p. 89). This conclusion is a frank disagreement with the reigning discontinuity theorists. This point explains Hall's emphasis on "continuity" and puts his choice of terms in the historical context of the past discontinuity theorists. The statement also provides the explanation for a brief, seemingly cryptic sentence that appears in the discussion of the continuity hypothesis in a coauthored popular book with his research assistant: "The dream world is neither discontinuous [i.e., Freudian] nor inverse [i.e., Jungian] in its relationship to the conscious world" (Hall & Nordby, 1972, p. 104). However, the concept of a "continuity hypothesis" was not introduced in the book on Kafka's dreams.

The Kafka book was followed a year later by Hall's study of 1,368 dreams that a child molester wrote down over a 4-year period between 1963 and 1967 for his own reasons; only later did he give them to a clinical psychologist, Alan Bell, who interviewed him at the prison mental hospital in which he was incarcerated (Bell & Hall, 1971). Because of the huge sample size, Hall was able to make many inferences that were for the most part supported by personality assessment instruments and clinical materials collected by Bell at the facility as well as through the dreamer's written replies to questions formulated by Bell and Hall (1971, Chapter 2).

In this study Hall drew on the earlier discovery that the frequencies of an element in a series or set of dream reports reveal the relative intensity of waking concerns (Hall & Van de Castle, 1966, pp. 13-14). This finding adds a quantitative precision to the concept of "concerns," which should not go unremarked here because it makes it possible to rank personal concerns and demonstrate in yet another way that dreams are not based on incorporations from everyday waking life. For example, if a man dreams far more frequently about his mother than is the case for the male norms, or than any other character in a dream series, as this dreamer did, "it is inferred that the mother plays an important role in his life," as was indeed the case in this instance (Bell & Hall, 1971, p. 117). There then follows the first mention of the continuity hypothesis, with the italics in the original: "This may be called the continuity hypothesis because it assumes there is a continuity between dreams and waking life" (Bell & Hall, 1971, p. 117).

It is also important to add that the quoted sentence is followed by a qualifying statement showing that further work was needed to refine the concept: "There are difficulties with this hypothesis as we have seen, but first let us reconsider some of the kinds of information that dreams provide" (Bell & Hall, 1971, p. 117). The "difficulties" that Hall alludes to concern the fact that the continuity is not always with both waking thought and behavior, but sometimes with waking thought only, which is one of the key reasons why the emphasis came to be on waking thought, not behavior, in later refinements of the concept (Domhoff, 1996, 2003). That is, a behavioral concomitant may or may not be present, but the same concern expressed in the dream reports is always present in waking thought.

The child molester study, although a major advance over the Kafka study, nonetheless had deficiencies, partly because Bell, reasonably enough, wanted to foreground the projective tests, paper-and-pencil personality tests, interviews, and clinical information he had collected to construct a portrait of the child molester's personality (see Bell & Hall, 1971, p. 8 for the different interests and the division of labor between the two authors). More importantly, however, the analysis was presented within a Freudian framework, which led among other things to Hall's inference that the complete absence of the dreamer's father from the dream reports must mean that his conceptions and concerns in relation to his father had been repressed (Bell & Hall, 1971, p. 73). He then concluded that this claim was supported by the child molester's belief that he had been sexually abused by his father at age 4 (Bell & Hall, 1971, pp. 24, 76-77, 90).

However, this is the kind of memory of the past that is difficult if not impossible to confirm, as shown by the numerous later studies of the fallibility of memory (e.g., see Bauer, 2013; Garry & Hayne, 2007, for overviews). This is perhaps even more the case with highly troubling "recovered" memories from childhood, most if not all of which prove to be inaccurate, and especially so if they are allegedly from before the age of 5 or 6 (e.g., Foley, 2013; Howe, 2000; Howe & Knott, 2015). They are constructed in various ways through the imaginative reworking of memories and suggestions, which are often due to pressures from legal investigators of alleged molestations or through interactions with therapists who believe that child molestation is widely prevalent and is perpetrated even by women working in nursery schools (e.g., Ceci, Bruck, & Battin, 2000; Hyman & Loftus, 2002; Loftus, Joslyn, & Polage, 1998; Loftus & Ketcham, 1994; Ofshe & Watters, 1994; Ornstein, Ceci, & Loftus, 1998; Strange, Clifasefi, & Garry, 2007).

Thus, later cognitive dream researchers minimized or entirely abandoned any inferences and questions about long-ago events that allegedly happened to the dreamer. In terms of the inferences that they do make, the focus is on ongoing personal concerns. At the same time, it was never doubted by cognitive theorists that many of these personal concerns were persistent ones that the dreamers believed to go back many decades, especially in terms of past relationships with parents and siblings (Domhoff, 1996, Chapters 7-8; 2003, Chapter 5). Therefore, they rejected any claim that past concerns had been repressed, only to be recalled much later with the help of hypnosis or psychotherapy and then labeled a recovered memory. By the same token, the zero-frequency hypothesis put forth in the case of the child molester, based on the concept of repression, for which there is no systematic empirical evidence, was also discarded by later cognitive dream researchers (Loftus et al., 1998; Loftus & Ketcham, 1994; Mazzoni & Loftus, 1998; Mazzoni, Loftus, Seitz, & Lynn, 1999; Ofshe & Watters, 1994).

The first complete statement of the continuity hypothesis was put forth in a popular book in 1972: " The wishes and fears that determine our actions and thoughts in everyday life also determine what we will dream about [italics added]" (Hall & Nordby, 1972, p. 104). Hall then did several other studies related to the continuity hypothesis, adding new wrinkles and evidence, until shortly before his death in 1985; most of these studies were not published. On the basis of these studies, his final published statement on the continuity hypotheses used the phrase "concerns and preoccupations" instead of "wishes and fears," which reflected his gradual distancing from the language of the two major psychodynamic theorists, Freud (1900) and Jung (1974): "The continuity hypothesis states that dreaming is continuous with waking life. That is, people will manifest in their dreams the concerns and preoccupations of their waking life [italics added]" (Hall, Domhoff, Blick, & Weesner, 1982, p. 193).

Hall's further development of the continuity hypothesis, and the changes in it by cognitive theorists, is traced out in greater detail in a chapter in Finding Meaning in Dreams entitled "The Continuity Between Dreams and Waking Life" (Domhoff, 1996, Chapter 8). In particular, this chapter spells out the mistaken inferences Hall drew and the lessons that he and later cognitive dream researchers learned from them. They are important in understanding how the concept evolved into a fully cognitive one, with no remnants of the psychodynamic elements in Hall's earlier theorizing.

For example, in the case of the child molester, Hall inferred (based on several dreams in which the dreamer was masturbating) that he was a frequent and compulsive masturbator. However, the dreamer said this was untrue and noted that he was able to resist urges to masturbate for weeks at a time. He thought masturbation was wrong and often felt depressed after he masturbated (Bell & Hall, 1971, pp. 25, 94). He worked hard to overcome his preoccupation with his body and was very interested in spirituality and meditation. Bell and Hall (1971, p. 96) therefore concluded that "an analysis of the dream content reveals very little about his defensive maneuvers," which means that he was able to resist masturbating in waking life. This distinction is a very useful one that was taken into account in future studies by those who followed in Hall's path. It is one of many pieces of evidence that refutes the claim that the continuity hypothesis has any necessary relationship to waking behavior. This evidence includes a more recent study also concluding that the frequency of sexual dreams was related to the frequency of waking sexual fantasies, but not to the frequency of masturbation or sexual relations (Schredl, Desch, Röming, & Spachmann, 2009).

Hall also did a study of 58 dreams from a neurotic patient in psychotherapy in which his 42 inferences were corroborated or rejected by the psychotherapist (Domhoff, 1996, pp. 171-176; Moss, 1970, Chapter 3). Most of his inferences proved to be correct, but it is his mistakes that were the most useful. In particular, he wrongly inferred on the basis of only one dream, a dream in which the patient and his brother were trapped in their mother's apartment (i.e., she was not actually present in the dream), that the dreamer had a negative relationship with his mother. This inference proved to be quite wrong. In effect, Hall overgeneralized, as he explained: "I figured that anyone who had such poor relations with women, including his wife, and then has a dream in which he is trapped in her [i.e., his mother's] apartment, must also have poor relations with his mother" (Domhoff, 1996, p. 175). The lesson here is that hostility toward a general category, such as women, should not be presumed to include specific significant others who are included in that category unless there is hostility toward them as well. In effect, Hall relied on psychodynamic theory in making this inference, as can be seen in his sentence quoted earlier in this paragraph, rather than relying on specific portrayals of interactions within several dream reports.

Hall performed a very informative study of an engineer in his early 30s, Karl, who sent him more than 1,000 dream reports and mailed him detailed answers to his inferences (Domhoff, 1996, pp. 178-181; Hall & Nordby, 1972, pp. 119-126). Once again, Hall's inferences were mostly correct, but it is the mistakes that are useful. First of all, Karl had many highly aggressive dreams, especially toward his father, so Hall inferred that he occasionally provoked fights and harbored generally angry feelings. However, Karl reported that he never engaged in fights and regarded himself as being a friendly, warmhearted, and peaceful person. In this instance, Hall made the opposite type of mistake to the one made with the neurotic patient. With the neurotic patient, Hall used hostile interactions with various women to infer that the dreamer disliked his mother, and he was wrong. With Karl he used hostility toward Karl's father (and mother and wife) to infer aggressive interactions with a wider range of people, and he was wrong again, this time because Karl's dream reports do not reveal that he is in general an angry, violent person. On the other hand, Karl repeatedly told Hall that he harbored great anger toward his father, mother, and wife; therefore, the general point once again is that inferences drawn from the analysis of dream reports concerning continuity with waking thoughts and personal concerns should focus on specific people and not on generalities.

On the basis of these and a few other studies discussed in the synthesis chapter, the continuity hypothesis was updated to include both conceptions and personal concerns, which more firmly links the emphasis on conceptions in Hall's (1953) original formulation of a cognitive theory of dreams to his later discovery of how well the frequency of various elements in a person's dream reports tracks her or his waking personal concerns:

In all, the findings presented in this chapter are good evidence for our claim that the conceptions and concerns found in dream content appear to be the same ones operating in waking life. The waking mind and the dreaming mind seem to be one and the same, which is a strong argument for the idea that there is meaning in dreams. (Domhoff, 1996, p. 189)

Studies beginning in the late 1990s fully demonstrated the new, fully cognitive conception of the continuity hypothesis. The largest and most detailed of these studies is based on 3,115 dream reports written down by a divorced woman ("Barb Sanders") over a period of nearly 37 years. However, the first 106 dreams were written down only sporadically during the first 19 of those years; thus, the analysis is for the most part based on 3,009 dreams documented over a period of 18 years and 4 months. This means that she averaged 3.5 dream reports per week during the later time period, when she had the time and motivation to document every dream she recalled. Therefore, she can be classified as a typical dream recaller. In addition to numerous Hall and Van de Castle (1966) content analyses, the study included interviews with the dreamer and four of her friends. The friends were included to serve as "judge and jury" if there were any differences between the investigator's inferences and the responses by the dreamer (in the event, there were very few in this case; Domhoff, 2003, Chapter 5). This study also reintroduced the idea that there are "discontinuities" in dream reports as well as continuities. However, they were not the kind of discontinuities claimed by the various psychodynamic discontinuity theorists of the past. On the basis of an examination of many of the discontinuities in this dream series, discontinuities were hypothesized to be related to possible figurative constructions, which remained poorly studied as of the end of 2016, and/or to possible cognitive glitches, which remain completely unstudied.

The original Barb Sanders study was later extended in various ways, including the addition of more than 1,000 of her subsequent dreams for some new analyses, but so much has been written about the overall results that little more will be said here (Bulkeley, 2009; Domhoff, 2010a). However, a highly original network analysis comparing her waking social networks and her network of dream characters, based on 4,254 dream reports documented over a 41-year period, is well worth noting (Han, 2014). It revealed that the social networks in her dream reports were small-world networks similar to those found in waking life, but her network of dream characters differed from those in her waking life. The people who were emotionally closest to her in waking life tended to appear in dreams together although they were not in the same social networks in waking life (Han, 2014, pp. 50, 67). These results, which appear to take the continuity hypothesis to a more abstract and quantitative level, along with the other findings based on the Barb Sanders series, including her constant rehashing of past relationships and other disappointments, belie any emphasis on the influence of daily events on dreaming and support the conclusion that dreams are not a mere incorporation of everyday waking activities.

It is also relevant to any discussion of the continuity hypothesis that studies of dream series using 40 standardized word strings (Bulkeley, 2012, 2014; Bulkeley & Domhoff, 2010) have lent independent support to the concept, which answers any criticisms of studies of dream series based on the Hall and Van de Castle (1966) coding system by critics of the cognitive version of the continuity hypothesis (Schredl, 2012, pp. 4-5). To take one good example from a comprehensive blind analysis that led to numerous correct inferences, a young woman who wrote down 223 of her dreams as a teenager, and another 63 in her early years of college, had more frequent (and upsetting) dreams about her parents and brother during her first year or two in college than she previously had. This led to the correct inference that she experienced more worry and stress relating to her family while in college than she previously had. As she explained in response to this inference:

My first semester at college was very difficult and I was extremely homesick. I also had a spike in my anxiety, which led me to seek counseling through the college. I ruminated and worried a lot, missed my family, and was sure that now that I was away at school, something bad would happen. (Bulkeley, 2012, p. 245)

As the investigator concluded, This finding highlights an important point about the continuity hypothesis: "Dreams accurately reflect emotional concerns but not necessarily actual events" (Bulkeley, 2012, p. 248). This researcher uses the word reflect , but the crucial difference from the incorporation theorists is that he stresses the reflection of concerns, not the reflection of various waking events.

Although the original studies that led to the continuity hypothesis were based on individual dream series, an impressive longitudinal study in which the investigators studied the participants in 1991 and 2000-2001 demonstrated considerable continuity between waking well-being measures and aspects of dream content (Pesant & Zadra, 2006). Then, too, in a study comparing 30-day dream diaries from 35 professional musicians and 30 nonmusicians, which also included a daily questionnaire concerning their involvement with music during the day, the musi- cians dreamt twice as often about music as did the nonmusicians, and the frequency of their musical dreams was greater if they became involved in music as young teenagers or earlier. Even more significant in terms of this article, the frequency of their musical dreams did not relate to the degree of their waking musical activity during the days they kept the dream diary; therefore, the musical dreams did not reflect current waking reality (Uga, Lemut, Zampi, Zilli, & Salzarulo, 2006). These two studies are important because they minimize or eliminate any concern that possible selection biases in self-motivated dream series account for the evidence for the continuity hypothesis.

On the other hand, the possibility that evidence for the incorporation of everyday experiences and passing daily concerns into dreams might be found in controlled studies has received no support. This conclusion first of all rests on a series of three studies using both laboratory-collected and home-collected dream reports to compare daytime concerns with dream reports collected that night. In the initial study, eight participants spent 8 nights each in the sleep laboratory and reported dreams from awakenings after the first rapid eye movement (REM) period of the night. The several judges could not match the dream reports with either the general thought samples or the expressions of significant concerns of that day, which the participants provided before falling asleep (Roussy et al., 1996). A second laboratory study involved 13 women participants who reported dreams after awakenings from three of the first four REM periods on each of 4 laboratory nights. Once again, judges were unable to match the dream reports with either waking thought samples or lists of five significant concerns from earlier in the day that were obtained before the participants went to sleep (Roussy, 1998). The third study simulated everyday conditions by asking 13 women students to write down, on 6 separate days, the events of the day before going to bed, and then to document any dreams they recalled upon awakening the next morning. Using a less complex matching task than in the first two studies, 14 independent women judges could only rarely match the thought samples with the dream reports (Roussy et al., 2000). It is also noteworthy in regard to the experiential incorporation hypothesis that two longitudinal laboratory studies of the dreams of children and adolescents found that they rarely dreamed of their most frequent daytime activities, watching TV and reading, writing, and learning in a classroom setting (Foulkes, 1982, 1999; Strauch, 2005).

In concluding this discussion of what the continuity hypothesis actually involves, it is far more specific, empirically developed, and refined over time than is understood by those who claim that the continuity hypothesis is about the influence of events from waking life on dreaming. As shown in this section, the initial studies leading to this new concept were based on personal dream journals, which are regarded as unobtrusive and nonreactive measures by researchers in personality, social, and community psychology (e.g., Allport, 1942; Baldwin, 1942; Johns, Coady, Chan, Farley, & Kansagra, 2013; Schwartz & Sechrest, 2000, pp. xi-xix; Webb, Campbell, Schwartz, Sechrest, & Grove, 1981; Whitley & Kite, 2013). They are more valuable than many experimentally oriented dream researchers seem to appreciate because they have not been influenced by the demand characteristics, expectancy effects, and social desirability effects that were shown decades ago to vitiate the results of many experimental studies to a far greater extent than many current experimentalists seem to remember (e.g., Kihlstrom, 2002; Orne, 1962; Rosenthal & Ambady, 1995; Rosenthal & Rosnow, 1969). That said, this section also has shown that two studies not based on self-motivated dream series support the continuity hypothesis as well (Pesant & Zadra, 2006; Uga et al., 2006).

Looking for Continuity in All of the Wrong Places

Although it was widely known by the late 1990s that the continuity hypothesis is narrowly focused on the continuity between conceptions and ongoing personal concerns in dreams and waking life, this point is completely ignored in the first full-length article that misunderstood its meaning (Schredl, 2003). The problems started in the first sentence of the abstract, which begins with the pejorative "so-called continuity hypothesis" and then proceeds to incorrectly define it, as shown in the following quotation. The second sentence in the quotation then criticizes this inaccurate and newly created definition of the concept as "very broad and vague:"

The so-called continuity hypothesis of dreaming states that waking experiences are reflected [wrong] in dreams. The formulation of the continuity hypothesis is very broad and vague [wrong], however, so that it seems necessary to investigate factors which might affect the incorporation rate of waking-life experiences [which is completely off base and irrelevant because the hypothesis says nothing about 'incorporation']. (Schredl, 2003, p. 26)

The first two sentences of the main body of the article then mistakenly link the origins of the continuity hypothesis to Freud's concept of the "day residue," which concerns the (usually minor) event from the previous day that Freud (1900, pp. 127, 366-368) claimed to be the starting point for every dream:

Already in 1900, Freud (1) reported that day residues (recent waking-life experiences) are common in dreams. This observation and subsequent empirical studies (overviews: 2-5) have led to the so-called continuity hypothesis of dreaming which states that waking experiences are reflected in dreams; in other words: dreaming is in continuity with waking life. (Schredl, 2003, p. 26)

Thus, in the space of just four sentences, the continuity hypothesis has been stood on its head. Dreams do not "reflect" waking-life experiences; for the most part they express (enact, embody, dramatize) personal conceptions and ongoing personal concerns relating to the important people and activities in the dreamers' waking lives. This hypothesis is not "very vague and broad" but was made so by the critic through a mischaracterization of it. Nor did it have its origins in Freud's (1900, p. 127) claims about the day residue; it says nothing about day residues and represents a major departure from the Freudian theory of dreams.

After wrongly summarizing the established continuity hypothesis, the article then proceeds to review the literature on the influence of (a) day residues, (b) the experimental manipulation of presleep events, and (c) laboratory references in dreams collected in sleep laboratories. It also examines (d) the degree to which ordinary daytime experiences are incorporated into dream content. However, all of these alleged incorporations are relatively rare, and some of them are trivial, as overviewed in the next section. In addition, the failure to find connections between the events of the day and dream reports in the three studies discussed at the end of the previous section is not addressed (Roussy, 1998; Roussy et al., 1996, 2000). Instead, one of those three studies is mentioned in a table concerning the frequency of references of the laboratory setting in REM dream reports collected in a sleep laboratory (Roussy et al., 1996; Schredl, 2003, p. 34).

Surprisingly, the critical review does not cite any of the original work on the continuity hypothesis by Hall and his coworkers (Bell & Hall, 1971; Hall & Lind, 1970; Hall & Nordby, 1972). Although it briefly mentions Finding Meaning in Dreams (Domhoff, 1996) as one of four sources providing "overviews" of "empirical studies" (Schredl, 2003, p. 26), it does not indicate that the definition of the concept in that book and the empirical evidence that it cited are completely at odds with its account. Nor is there any mention of the large body of work on dream series that is presented in detail in Finding Meaning in Dreams (Domhoff, 1996). Despite these many problematic aspects to Schredl's (2003) original critical article, there is no criticism of any of the many omissions and distortions in it, or even any mention of them, by any of the authors who had cited it and made use of its redefinition of the continuity hypothesis by the end of 2016 (e.g., King & DeCicco, 2009; Malinowski & Horton, 2011, 2014; Revonsuo et al., 2015; Sándor et al., 2016; Selterman et al., 2014).

In response to criticism of his first analysis of the continuity hypothesis (e.g., Bulkeley, 2011; Domhoff, 2011a), Schredl (2012, p. 1) quotes four paragraphs from the popular book by Hall and Nordby (1972), which he had originally ignored, to claim that the authors "clearly indicate that the continuity hypothesis was defined very broadly and clearly goes beyond the notions of conceptions and concerns suggested by Domhoff as the most important aspects of continuity." Although these four paragraphs include the original psychodynamic definition of the continuity hypothesis that was cited earlier in this article ("The wishes and fears that determine our actions and thoughts in everyday life also determine what we will dream about"), which renders his other (often mistaken) claims irrelevant, the crucial point in terms of making any theoretical advances is that the concept had been refined and improved in the ensuing decades (Domhoff, 1996, Chapter 8), as demonstrated in the previous section. By resorting to a debatable exegesis of an outdated text instead of formulating one or more new alternative hypotheses, such as an experiential incorporation hypothesis, this kind of analysis obscures the fact that the present-day cognitive version of the continuity hypothesis abandons some of Hall's original claims and builds in part on work by other cognitive theorists (e.g., Antrobus, 1978; Domhoff, 1996, pp. 7, 209-212; Foulkes, 1982, 1985; Klinger, 1971).

Schredl (2012, pp. 4-5) goes further astray by criticizing the coding categories for emotions in the Hall and Van de Castle (1966) coding system because they allegedly underestimate the frequency of emotions in dreams and overstate the percentage of emotions that are negative. Although there are strong methodological and empirical reasons for doubting this claim (e.g., Domhoff, 2005, in press, Chapters 1 and 6; Foulkes, Sullivan, Kerr, & Brown, 1988), the important point here is that none of the studies of personal concerns was based on emotion codings. Some of the studies included codings for aggressive and friendly interactions, but aggression and friendliness are not among the five to seven basic emotions that are generally agreed upon by research psychologists (e.g., anger, apprehension/fear, sadness, disgust/contempt, surprise, love, and joy; e.g., Ekman, 1992, 2016; Shaver, Schwartz, Kirson, & O'Connor, 1987). On the basis of these points, it can be seen that any emphasis on the incorporation of waking emotional experiences into dreams is an offshoot of Schredl's (2006, 2012) experiential incorporation hypothesis, which could be called the emotion assimilation hypothesis to distinguish it from the continuity hypothesis (e.g., Malinowski & Horton, 2014, 2016; Schredl, 2006; van Rijn, Eichenlaub, & Blagrove, 2016).

A year after Schredl's (2003) original summary article modifying and criticizing the continuity hypothesis appeared, Schredl and Hofmann (2003) repeated the same inaccurate claims about the definition of the continuity hypothesis in the context of a study that led to many similar studies by several dream researchers. It is based on 2-week dream diaries that were kept by 133 participants (104 women and 29 men). At the end of the 2 weeks, the participants were asked via a questionnaire to estimate the amount of time they had spent during the previous 2 weeks in

a variety of daily activities such as using a computer for working, playing computer games, making telephone calls, spending time with the spouse, reading (divided into leisure time and occupational/studying), driving a car, watching TV, riding a bus/tramway, walking, doing a job, calculating, talking with friends, writing, and being in nature. (Schredl & Hofmann, 2003, p. 301)

It apparently did not seem relevant to these researchers that accurate after-the-fact assessments of the time spent on these activities over a 2-week period would be a considerable feat of memory, although one of the coauthors later acknowledged that this approach "suffers from possible recall problems" (Schredl, 2012, p. 5).

On the basis of 443 dream reports from the 133 participants, the investigators found a range of correlations between the amount of time spent in various waking activities and the frequency with which those activities appeared in the dream sample. They explain their mixed and generally negative findings on the basis of the generality of the continuity hypothesis (without saying that one of the coauthors had created this general, vague, and inaccurate definition) and various methodological problems. They raise these criticisms without even mentioning the unlikelihood that a retrospective questionnaire can provide anything but vague guesswork if modern-day memory research by psychologists has any merit. They then conclude that "the continuity hypothesis in its present general form is not valid [italics added] and should be elaborated and tested in a more specific way" (Schredl & Hofmann, 2003, p. 299).

The conclusion that the continuity hypothesis is not valid is then added to the bill of particulars put forth by dream theorists who focus on the possibility that dreams are a kind of social rehearsal as threat simulations (Revonsuo, 2000) and/or as social simulations (Revonsuo et al., 2015). However, in doing so they ignore the original definition of the continuity hypothesis by claiming it states that dreaming is a "passive mirroring of recent waking life" and therefore can be tested by assuming that "dreams represent a random sample of recent waking experience (or a random sample of their memory representations)" (Revonsuo et al., 2015, p. 10). Nor do the simulation theorists (or the two-dozen other investigators who cite the Schredl & Hofmann, 2003 study) offer the slightest criticism of it, not even for the use of a retrospective questionnaire.

Furthermore, the simulation theorists do not adequately comprehend the implications of the findings on consistency in a person's dreams over months, years, and decades, based on nearly two dozen studies, which reveal that people tend to differentially dramatize (not passively reflect) the same ongoing concerns about interpersonal relationships and favorite avocations on a very regular basis (Domhoff, 1996, Chapter 7; 2010a; Hall & Nordby, 1972, Chapter 5). The detection of repeated patterns, especially in instances involving frequent dreams about failed past relationships, or about deceased love ones, is a major addition to the already strong evidence that calls into question any claim that dreams are primarily a reflection of recent events (Domhoff, 1996, Chapter 7; 2003, Chapter 5; 2015; in press, Chapter 3).

The inadequacies of the Schredl and Hofmann (2003) study, and the simulation theorists' misuse of it, to one side, studies based on retrospective estimates of time spent in waking events continued to be the predominant basis on which Schredl and his coworkers studied experiential incorporations. In a backward step from the Schredl and Hofmann (2003) study, many of these studies did not even involve keeping a dream diary. For example, in a study of 82 truck drivers that was said to support the experiential distortion of the continuity hypothesis, the participants were asked to estimate the amount of time they spent driving a truck each week, the frequency with which they dreamt, and the percentage of their dreams that were about truck driving (Schredl, Funkhouser, & Arn, 2005, p. 181). Another study asked 131 college students, some of who were athletes, to estimate the frequency with which they dreamt, the amount of time they spent playing sports and reading, and the percentage of their dreams that involved sports or reading (Schredl & Erlacher, 2008, p. 268-269). Still another study was said to support the continuity hypothesis because the students who replied on a questionnaire concerning typical dreams that they had killed someone in a dream had higher hostility scores on a personality test (Schredl & Mathes, 2014, p. 178).

In a questionnaire study of music and dreams, 144 students, including music students, estimated the time they spent in music-related activities in waking life and the frequency with which they dreamt about music. The investigators found that "the amount of time invested in music activities during the day is directly related to the percentage of music dreams, thereby confirming the continuity hypothesis" (Vogelsang, Anold, Schormann, Wübbelmann, & Schredl, 2016, p. 132). However, they then note the "possible recall biases regarding retrospective measures" and suggest future studies using dream diaries (Vogelsang et al., 2016, p. 132). Because there is already a dream-diary study showing that the amount of time involved in music during the day did not relate to daily estimates of the frequency of music dreams for musicians (Uga et al., 2006), a study the authors duly cite, it seems unlikely that their music study, based as it is on estimates in response to a retrospective questionnaire, or any of the studies cited in the previous paragraph, can be taken seriously as studies of the continuity hypothesis, even for their version of it.

Questionnaire studies that ask for estimates about dream recall frequency, dream content, and time spent in various waking activities are simply correlational studies of various dimensions of waking thoughts and beliefs. Because very few people have any detailed knowledge of their dreams, studies of the current beliefs that people have about them are probably based on a combination of cultural stereotypes, personality variables, dreams recalled within the previous few days, selective recall of a few memorable dreams, and the whims of the moment (e.g., see Beaulieu-Prévost & Zadra, 2005a, 2005b, 2007, 2015; Bernstein & Belicki, 1996; Bernstein & Roberts, 1995).

The Rarity of Everyday Influences on Dreaming

According to cognitively oriented dream researchers, the appearance of daily events in dreams is a relatively minor matter because dreams are dramatic simulations based on the human ability to imagine (e.g., Antrobus, 1978, 2000; Foulkes, 1985, 1999; Hall, 1991; Reinsel, Antrobus, &Wollman, 1992). Their claims are fully supported by the three careful studies of the issue discussed in an earlier section (Roussy, 1998; Roussy et al., 1996, 2000). They are also supported by the rarity of any evidence for the influence of daily experience on dream content in many other kinds of studies.

For example, in the case of day residue, five detailed studies from decades ago, one of which involved a study of a lengthy dream series that included mentions of day residues, demonstrated that only approximately half of dreams contain even the slightest day residue that can be identified by the dreamer (Botman & Crovitz, 1990; Harlow & Roll, 1992; Hartmann, 1968; Marquardt, Bonato, & Hoffmann, 1996; Nielsen & Powell, 1992).

As far as stimulus-incorporation studies, early laboratory dream researchers found that it is very difficult to influence dream content with either presleep stimuli, such as fear-arousing or sensual movies, or with concurrent stimuli administered during REM periods, such as sounds or the whispering of the names of significant people in the dreamers' lives (e.g., Berger, 1963; Dement, 1965; Dement, Kahn, & Roffwarg, 1965; Foulkes, 1996; Foulkes & Rechtschaffen, 1964). Moreover, the impact of external stimuli on dreams may be exaggerated because the criteria for incorporation were very loose in several studies; sometimes, alleged metaphoric expressions of the stimulus, which are notoriously difficult to validate, were counted as correspondences (see Arkin & Antrobus, 1991, for a critical review).

Suggestions during sleep related to the dreamer's current concerns (which may or may not be very personal or long felt) fared no better in a laboratory study. In this carefully controlled study, seven young adult men each slept in the laboratory for 4 consecutive nights: 1 night for adaptation and 3 for studies of their incorporation of recorded words that were played several times during different REM periods. Some of the stimulus words related to their current concerns, as ascertained via a questionnaire, and some did not (Hoelscher, Klinger, & Barta, 1981, p. 89). Fifty-six of 59 REM awakenings yielded a dream report. Independent judges concluded that there were only five instances of incorporated current concerns, a very meager return (Hoelscher et al., 1981, p. 90).

One exception to these generalizations about the small impacts of external stimuli can be found in a pilot study in which the researcher used a rough equivalent of a blood-pressure cuff to apply increasing pressure during REM periods to the legs of four acquaintances of the researcher who agreed to participate; this somatosensory stimulation was frequently incorporated as simple, direct sensations of pressure or squeezing (Nielsen, 1993). Another exception may concern the influence of the smell of rotten eggs on dream content (Schredl, Atanasova, et al., 2009; Schredl, Hoffmann, Sommer, & Stuck, 2014). Contrary to what these investigators seem to believe, their studies using extraordinary stimuli, which are rarely if ever encountered in ordinary daily life, reveal just how unlikely it is that the events of the day are incorporated into dreams.

On the basis of a consideration of the laboratory dream research literature over a period of nearly 40 years, a dream researcher who did several studies that tried to influence dream content later concluded that

Probably the most general conclusion to be reached from a wide variety of disparate stimuli employed and analyses undertaken is that dreams are relatively autonomous, or 'isolated,' mental phenomena, in that they are not readily susceptible to either induction or modification by immediate pre-sleep manipulation, at least those within the realm of possibility in ethical human experimentation. (Foulkes, 1996, p. 614)

Nor have more recent studies of laboratory incorporations shown any higher percentages, and some of them suggest that personal concerns are the key reason for these few incorporations. The rarity of incorporations, even during the sleep-onset period, is demonstrated in a study in which participants played a computer game ( Tetris ) for 7-9 h a day for 3-4 days in a row (Stickgold, 2003, pp. 10-14). Although 64% of the 27 participants reported at least one incorporation after being "automatically and repetitively prompted for mentation reports during the first hour of attempted sleep," the actual number of incorporations was only 9.8% of all probes for 12 novice players and 4.8% for 10 experienced players; it was 7.2% for 5 participants suffering from profound amnesia, who were included because they might report imagistic evidence of playing the game although they could not remember they had played it (Stickgold, 2003, pp. 10-11). Although the investigator was gratified by the differences among the three groups because he thinks they support his theoretical assumptions, the crucial point as far as this article is concerned is that these figures are reminiscent of the low levels of incorporations found in earlier studies and once again are based on an experimental manipulation that far exceeds the bounds of everyday life (Arkin & Antrobus, 1991).

In a study in which 50 participants took part in a task in which they individually learned how to negotiate a virtual maze on a computer screen and then took a nap, only 4 of them reported thoughts and images after awakenings that related to the task they had learned. Three of them "reported task-related mentation at sleep onset (following at least one minute of continuous sleep), whereas the fourth reported a maze-related dream after awakening from stage 2 sleep at the end of the nap period" (Wamsley, Tucker, Payne, Benavides, & Stickgold, 2010, p. 850). Once again, this is a very meager amount of incorporation for an intense daytime experience (a difficult learning task) that had taken place not long before their naps. Moreover, tasks such as the Tetris game and the virtual maze negotiation may be incorporated on rare occasions because they are "related to concerns about pre-sleep task performance," which is consistent with the original cognitive meaning of the continuity hypothesis (Blagrove, Ruby, & Eichenlaub, 2013, p. 609). Put another way, many people feel personally threatened when they are asked to perform a challenging task.

Similar conclusions seem to follow from a study in which four students (a very small sample size) taking a 6-week second-language immersion class in French each slept in the laboratory 4 times (once before the class began, twice during the 6 weeks of instruction, and once after the class ended). The dream reports mentioning the attempt to learn French portray frustration and failure in grappling with what the person was trying to learn, not a simple incorporation of the participants learning French in the classroom and speaking French in the dormitory and dining hall. As the researchers who performed this work put it, the findings "support the notion that incorporations of learning experiences into dreams that contain frustration and anxiety do not appear to be associated with the learning process [italics added] but instead may be a reflection of obstacles encountered" (De Koninck, Wong, & Hébert, 2012, p. 190). In other words, they are about a frustrating waking concern, a new personal concern they have developed in an unusual and challenging environment in which the expectations as far as learning are very high.

Turning to studies of the appearance of the laboratory setting in dreams collected in the sleep laboratory, Schredl (2003, p. 35) is mistaken in claiming that "the experimental setting strongly affects dream content" and that "participation in a laboratory experiment is 'real' stress." In fact, after one or two adaptation nights, during which portions of the left hemisphere are now known to be more alert than on later nights in a new place (Tamaki, Bang, Watanabe, & Sasaki, 2014, 2016; Tamaki, Nittono, Hayashi, & Hori, 2005), the percentages for incorporation then decline to a low level because the participants know what to expect. However, he may be right that "the incorporation rates are higher than those for experimental manipulation of the pre-sleep situation" (Schredl, 2003, p. 35).

In the best-controlled early study of the effects of the laboratory on dreaming and dream content, it was determined that only 10.6% of the dream reports from 11 college male participants included any portion of text, however brief, that related to the experimental situation. This figure did not vary from the first night they were awakened, after 3 adjustment nights in which they were not awakened, until the end of the participants' involvement in the study; furthermore, only 6.2% of the dream reports contained a significant amount of laboratory-related content, a fact that is also reported in Schredl's (2003, p. 34) assessment of the evidence for everyday incorporations (Hall, 1967, pp. 200, 202-206). Of 32 dream reports with laboratory elements, 13 contained anxiety or hostility in relation to the experiment or the investigators (40.6%), which suggested negative concerns. Surprisingly, the investigator found that the participants who developed the most interest in the study (as evidenced by the questions they asked before and after experimental nights) dreamed most frequently about the laboratory setting, which suggests a positive concern with the study on their part (Hall, 1967, p. 198).

Ironically, this study also provided inadvertent support for the not-yet-formulated continuity hypothesis in that several participants dreamt very frequently about their major waking interests, dwarfing the handful of dreams that included laboratory elements. For example, 30% of the 50 dream reports from a participant preoccupied with sports cars included a sports car; a person focused on a small singing group to which he belonged dreamt about it in 40% of 35 reports; and a person whose chief avocation involved airplanes dreamt about them in 32.3% of his reports (Hall, 1967, pp. 204-205).

Nor is there any evidence that the laboratory situation is continuously stressful even for children ages 4-10, as shown through careful monitoring of their prebedtime behavior and sleep patterns in both longitudinal and cross-sectional studies (Foulkes, 1982; Foulkes, Hollifield, Sullivan, Bradley, & Terry, 1990). The 14 preschool children in the longitudinal study were rated as calm or relaxed on 79% of the nights and as extremely anxious on only 5.4% of the nights. Their median time to fall asleep was 20 min; the same children took only 12 min when they returned 2 years later. The median number of spontaneous night awakenings was 1 or 0, and the median time awake during the night was 8 min or less (Foulkes, 1982, pp. 33-34). In a cross-sectional study involving 80 children within a month of their fifth through eighth birthdays, the participants scored low on a 5-point anxiety scale that was administered on each visit and on average fell asleep 12.5-14.5 min after the lights were turned out (Foulkes et al., 1990, p. 454).

Finally, there are well-designed studies of the degree to which everyday daily life is reflected in dream reports. In these studies the participants kept 1-week or 2-week records of the major daily events, major waking concerns, and personally significant events in their waking lives, as well as of any dreams they recalled. Therefore, these studies may be more accurate than the numerous studies based on retrospective estimates of time spent on a certain activity. However, they involve a different kind of judging task that has its own methodological difficulties, leading to a complex mix of findings that will need to be sorted out in future replication studies before they can be used to balance out the overwhelmingly negative results in relation to the experiential incorporation hypothesis. Specifically, in these studies the participants are asked at the end of the data-collection phase to go through the dream diaries and their record of daily events to make judgments on the correspondences they see between dreams and waking concerns and experiences and whether the concerns and experiences are from the same day as the dream occurred or from any of the days before the dream occurred (e.g., Henley-Einion & Blagrove, 2014; van Rijn et al., 2015).

These studies sometimes show some evidence for the inclusion of recorded events from the same day as the dream (day residue) and for the appearance of recorded events in dreams that occur 5-7 days later (the "dream-lag effect"). However, the results vary depending on whether participants "give a single rating to the degree of correspondence between each dream report and each diary record" or "rated separately the intensity of as many correspondences as they could identify between each dream report and each diary record" (Henley-Einion & Blagrove, 2014, p. 71). In the single-rating design, it is uncertain as to "how participants were making these global judgments"; as for the methodology using multiple correspondences, any statistically significant evidence of incorporations disappears, perhaps because some participants "have an excessive propensity to connect events" (Henley-Einion & Blagrove, 2014, pp. 72, 87).

However, it was then found that there is a statistically significant day-residue effect for the group of participants who identify less than the median number of overall correspondences, but why this would be so is not clear. Thus, this unanticipated finding for below-median responders needs to be replicated, and then further studies would be necessary to understand why low-responding participants would be more accurate than those who provide an above-median number of overall correspondences (Henley-Einion & Blagrove, 2014, p. 72).

In short, methodological issues make it uncertain as to whether statistically significant inclusions of thoughts, events, and experience from daily life have been demonstrated in these more recent and well-designed studies. Moreover, there are some indications that any incorporations that do occur in these more recent studies lend support to the cognitive version of the continuity hypothesis. In one of the most complex and best-controlled studies of this type, based on both laboratory and home-collected REM dream reports, the presence of the dream-lag effect "is dependent on the salience or personal importance of waking life events" (van Rijn et al., 2015, p. 107). This type of finding is also reported in a study of 2-week dream diaries and daily events diaries from 32 participants by two researchers who adhere to the emotion assimilation hypothesis; they conclude that "major daily activities were included significantly less than the combination of personally significant experiences, major concerns, and novel experiences" (Malinowski & Horton, 2014, p. 31).

As this overview shows, these studies reveal that daily events and experimental manipulations have very little influence on dream content. Metaphorically speaking, it is as if highly sophisticated statistical investigators reported after performing an exhaustive multivariate regression analysis that they had explained approximately 5-7% of the variance. However, if the most recent incorporation studies (Henley-Einion & Blagrove, 2014; Malinowski & Horton, 2014; van Rijn et al., 2015) can be replicated, then the small number of personally significant experiential incorporations would be a useful augmentation to the version of the continuity hypothesis that is consistent with recent theorizing by cognitive psychologists (Domhoff, 2003, in press; Foulkes, 1985, 2017; Foulkes & Domhoff, 2014).

As this article fully documents, the continuity hypothesis is a precisely defined cognitive concept focused on a person's conceptions and concerns, with concerns referring to a person's primary personal interests and preoccupations of both a positive and negative variety, many of which may extend back to their college years in the case of some adults that have been studied (Domhoff, in press, Chapters 3-4). As such, this concept is an important part of the effort to develop a neurocognitive theory of dreams that envisions dreaming as a form of spontaneous thought, far removed from the theoretical tradition of stimulus-response psychology, a tradition that naturally leads to a focus on the incorporation of events from daily life (e.g., Antrobus, 1978; Antrobus et al., 1970; Domhoff, 1996, pp. 210-212; 2010b; Domhoff & Fox, 2015; Foulkes, 1985, 1999; Foulkes & Domhoff, 2014; Fox et al., 2013; Reinsel et al., 1992). Therefore, the continuity hypothesis should be distinguished from the broadly defined "experiential incorporation hypothesis" created by Schredl (2003) and endorsed by many others (e.g., Malinowski & Horton, 2014; Revonsuo et al., 2015; Sándor et al., 2016; Selterman et al., 2014), which encompasses day residues, stimuli-induced incorporations within the laboratory setting, incorporations of the laboratory setting into dream reports collected in a sleep laboratory, and the appearance of everyday experiences from recent daily life.

Because of the very different theoretical orientations and methods that experiential incorporation theorists (e.g., Schredl, 2003; Schredl, 2012) and social rehearsal/simulation theorists (Revonsuo, 2000; Revonsuo et al., 2015) use in studying the relationship between waking and dreaming, and out of respect for the difficulties of developing a new theory in any research field, these dream researchers should adopt another label for the hypothesis they favor over the cognitive version of the continuity hypothesis. The concept of a continuity hypothesis owes its provenance to the cognitive tradition of dream researchers, who are trying to develop a new theory of dreams; therefore, the concept should not be redefined and diluted, which generates lack of clarity and confusion. The cognitively oriented dream theories are as independent from the psychodynamic discontinuity theories of the prelaboratory era as they are from the experiential incorporation and emotion assimilation hypotheses that flourish at the present time.

It may seem unusual that a dream researcher whose work is being critiqued in this article would be a coauthor of an article that directly states that his view of the continuity hypothesis is incorrect. However, he is a coauthor on that 2005-2006 article because he kindly provided the set of dream reports that is the basis for the empirical analysis in that article. Although he had the opportunity to read and comment on a draft version of it, he did not comment. The critique of the emphasis on experience in the article reads as follows, with the italics in the original published article:

More theoretically, the comparison of dream content with waking life suggests that dreams express our conceptions of the people and activities that concern us in waking life (Domhoff, 2003), not merely our experiences in waking life. This distinction between conceptions and experiences is a crucial one because Hall and Nordby's (1972) evidence and line of reasoning lead to a cognitive theory of dreams, whereas an emphasis on experiences in waking life implies a more environmentalistic or behavioristic theory. (Domhoff et al., 2006, p. 277)

Allport, G. (1942). The use of personal documents in psychological science . New York, NY: Social Science Research Council.

Antrobus, J. (1978). Dreaming for cognition. In A. Arkin, J. S. Antrobus, & S. J. Ellman (Eds.), The mind in sleep: Psychology and psychophysiology (1st ed., pp. 569-581). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

Antrobus, J. (2000). Theories of dreaming. In M. Kryger, T. Roth, & W. Dement (Eds.), Principles and practices of sleep medicine (3rd ed., pp. 472-481). Philadelphia, PA: Saunders.

Antrobus, J. S., Singer, J. L., Goldstein, S., & Fortgang, M. (1970). Mindwandering and cognitive structure. Transactions of the New York Academy of Sciences , 32 , 242-252. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.2164-0947.1970.tb02056.x

Arkin, A., & Antrobus, J. (1991). The effects of external stimuli applied prior to and during sleep on sleep experience. In S. J. Ellman & J. S. Antrobus (Eds.), The mind in sleep: Psychology and psychophysiology (2nd ed., pp. 265-307). New York, NY: Wiley.

Baldwin, A. (1942). Personal structure analysis: A statistical method for investigating the single personality. The Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology , 37 , 163-183. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0061697

Bauer, P. (2013). Memory. In P. Zelazo (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of developmental psychology: Vol. 1. Body and mind (pp. 503-541). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

Beaulieu-Prévost, D., & Zadra, A. (2005a). Dream recall frequency and attitude towards dreams: A reinterpretation of the relation. Personality and Individual Differences , 38 , 919-927. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.paid.2004.06.017

Beaulieu-Prévost, D., & Zadra, A. (2005b). How dream recall frequency shapes people's beliefs about the content of their dreams. North American Journal of Psychology , 7 , 253-264.

Beaulieu-Prévost, D., & Zadra, A. (2007). Absorption, psychological boundaries and attitude towards dreams as correlates of dream recall: Two decades of research seen through a meta-analysis. Journal of Sleep Research , 16 , 51-59. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1365-2869.2007.00572.x

Beaulieu-Prévost, D., & Zadra, A. (2015). When people remember dreams they never experienced: A study of the malleability of dream recall over time. Dreaming , 25 , 18-31. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0038788

Bell, A., & Hall, C. (1971). The personality of a child molester: An analysis of dreams . Chicago, IL: Aldine.

Berger, R. J. (1963). Experimental modification of dream content by meaningful verbal stimuli. The British Journal of Psychiatry , 109 , 722-740. http://dx.doi.org/10.1192/bjp.109.463.722

Bernstein, D. M., & Belicki, K. (1996). On the psychometric properties of retrospective dream content questionnaires. Imagination, Cognition and Personality , 15 , 351-364. http://dx.doi.org/10.2190/R1FRYHF7-EVG9-UDJT

Bernstein, D. M., & Roberts, B. (1995). Assessing dreams through self-report questionnaires: Relations with past research and personality. Dreaming , 5 , 13-27. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0094420

Blagrove, M., & Akehurst, L. (2000). Personality and dream recall frequency: Further negative findings. Dreaming , 10 , 139-148. http://dx.doi.org/10.1023/A:1009482223115

Blagrove, M., Ruby, P., & Eichenlaub, J.-B. (2013). Dreams are made of memories, but maybe not for memory. Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 36 , 609-610. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X13001222

Botman, H., & Crovitz, H. F. (1990). Dream reports and autobiographical memory. Imagination, Cognition and Personality , 9 , 213-224. http://dx.doi.org/10.2190/FL4H-TLHV-R5DV-0WDM

Bulkeley, K. (2009). The religious content of dreams: A new scientific foundation. Pastoral Psychology , 58 , 93-106. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11089-008-0180-8

Bulkeley, K. (2011). Testing the continuity hypothesis. International Journal of Dream Research , 4 , 48-49.

Bulkeley, K. (2012). Dreaming in adolescence: A 'blind' word search of a teenage girl's dream series. Dreaming , 22 , 240-252. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0030253

Bulkeley, K. (2014). Digital dream analysis: A revised method. Consciousness and Cognition: An International Journal , 29 , 159-170. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2014.08.015

Bulkeley, K., & Domhoff, G. W. (2010). Detecting meaning in dream reports: An extension of a word search approach. Dreaming , 20 , 77-95. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0019773

Ceci, S. J., Bruck, M., & Battin, D. B. (2000). The suggestibility of children's testimony. In D. Bjorklund (Ed.), False-memory creation in children and adults: Theory, research, and implications (pp. 169-201). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. De Koninck, J., Wong, C., & Hébert, G. (2012). Types of dream incorporations of language learning and learning efficiency. Journal of Sleep Research , 21 , 190.

Dement, W. (1965). An essay on dreams: The role of physiology in understanding their nature. In T. Newcomb (Ed.), New directions in psychology II (pp. 135-257). New York, NY: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.

Dement, W. C., Kahn, E., & Roffwarg, H. P. (1965). The influence of the laboratory situation on the dreams of the experimental subject. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease , 140 , 119-131. http://dx.doi.org/10.1097/00005053-196502000-00002

Domhoff, G. W. (1996). Finding Meaning in Dreams: A Quantitative Approach. New York, NY: Plenum Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4899-0298-6

Domhoff, G. W. (2001). A new neurocognitive theory of dreams. Dreaming , 11 , 13-33. http://dx.doi.org/10.1023/A:1009464416649

Domhoff, G. W. (2003). The scientific study of dreams: Neural networks, cognitive development, and content analysis . Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/10463-000

Domhoff, G. W. (2005). The content of dreams: Methodologic and theoretical implications. In M.

Kryger, T. Roth, & W. Dement (Eds.), Principles and practices of sleep medicine (4th ed., pp. 522-534). Philadelphia, PA: Elsevier Saunders. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/B0-72-160797-7/50049-5

Domhoff, G. W. (2007). Realistic simulation and bizarreness in dream content: Past findings and suggestions for future research. In D. Barrett & P. McNamara (Eds.), The new science of dreaming: Content, recall, and personality correlates (Vol. 2, pp. 1-27). Westport, CT: Praeger.

Domhoff, G. W. (2010a). Barb Sanders: Our best case to date. The Quantitative Study of Dreams. Retrieved from http://psych.ucsc.edu/dreams/Findings/barb_sanders.html

Domhoff, G. W. (2010b). Dream content is continuous with waking thought, based on preoccupations, concerns, and interests. Sleep Medicine Clinics , 5 , 203-215. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.jsmc.2010.01.010

Domhoff, G. W. (2011a). Dreams are embodied simulations that dramatize conceptions and concerns: The continuity hypothesis in empirical, theoretical, and historical context. International Journal of Dream Research , 4 , 50-62.

Domhoff, G. W. (2011b). The neural substrate for dreaming: Is it a subsystem of the default network? Consciousness and Cognition: An International Journal, 20, 1163-1174. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2011.03.001

Domhoff, G. W. (2015). Dreaming as embodied simulation: A widower dreams of his deceased wife. Dreaming , 25 , 232-256. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0039291

Domhoff, G. W. (in press). The Emergence of Dreaming: Mind-Wandering, Embodied Simulation, and The Default Network. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

Domhoff, G. W., & Fox, K. C. (2015). Dreaming and the default network: A review, synthesis, and counterintuitive research proposal. Consciousness and Cognition: An International Journal , 33 , 342-353. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2015.01.019

Domhoff, G. W., Meyer-Gomes, K., & Schredl, M. (2006). Dreams as the expression of conceptions and concerns: A comparison of German and American college students. Imagination, Cognition and Personality , 25 , 269-282. http://dx.doi.org/10.2190/FC3Q-2YMR-9A5F-N52M

Domhoff, G. W., & Schneider, A. (2008). Studying dream content using the archive and search engine on DreamBank.net. Consciousness and Cognition: An International Journal , 17 , 1238-1247. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2008.06.010

Ekman, P. (1992). An argument for basic emotions. Cognition and Emotion , 6 , 169-200. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/02699939208411068

Ekman, P. (2016). What scientists who study emotion agree about. Perspectives on Psychological Science , 11 , 31-34. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/1745691615596992

Foley, M. A. (2013). Children's source monitoring of memories for imagination. In M. Taylor (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of the development of imagination (pp. 94-112). New York, NY: Oxford University Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195395761.013.0007

Foulkes, D. (1982). Children's dreams: Longitudinal studies . New York, NY: Wiley.

Foulkes, D. (1985). Dreaming: A cognitive-psychological analysis . Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

Foulkes, D. (1996). Dream research: 1953-1993. Sleep: Journal of Sleep Research & Sleep Medicine , 19 , 609-624.

Foulkes, D. (1999). Children's dreaming and the development of consciousness . Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Foulkes, D. (2017). Dreaming, reflective consciousness, and feelings in the preschool child. Dreaming , 27 , 1-13. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/drm0000040

Foulkes, D., & Domhoff, G. W. (2014). Bottom-up or top-down in dream neuroscience? A top-down critique of two bottom-up studies. Consciousness and Cognition: An International Journal , 27 , 168-171. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2014.05.002

Foulkes, D., Hollifield, M., Sullivan, B., Bradley, L., & Terry, R. (1990). REM dreaming and cognitive skills at ages 5-8: A cross-sectional study. International Journal of Behavioral Development , 13 , 447-465. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/016502549001300404

Foulkes, D., & Rechtschaffen, A. (1964). Presleep determinants of dream content: Effects of two films. Perceptual and Motor Skills , 19 , 983-1005. http://dx.doi.org/10.2466/pms.1964.19.3.983

Foulkes, D., Sullivan, B., Kerr, N., & Brown, L. (1988). Appropriateness of dream feelings to dreamed situations. Cognition and Emotion , 2 , 29-39. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/02699938808415227

Fox, K., Nijeboer, S., Solomonova, E., Domhoff, G. W., & Christoff, K. (2013). Dreaming as mind wandering: Evidence from functional neuroimaging and first-person content reports. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience , 7 , 412. http://dx.doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2013.00412.eCollection02013

French, T., & Fromm, E. (1964). Dream Interpretation: A New Approach . New York, NY: Basic Books.

Freud, S. (1900). The interpretation of Dreams (J. Crick, Trans.). London, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.

Freud, S. (1901). On dreams (Vol. 5). London, United Kingdom: Hogarth Press.

Fromm, E. (1951). The Forgotten Language . New York, NY: Grove Press.

Garry, M., & Hayne, H. (2007). Do justice and let the sky fall: Elizabeth F. Loftus and her contributions to science, law, and academic freedom . Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

Gibbs, R. (1994). The poetics of mind: Figurative thought, language, and understanding . New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

Hall, C. (1953). A cognitive theory of dreams. Journal of General Psychology , 49 , 273-282. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00221309.1953.9710091

Hall, C. (1954). A primer of Freudian psychology . New York, NY: New American Library. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/10640-000

Hall, C. (1956). Current trends in research on dreams. In D. Brower & L. Abt (Eds.), Progress in clinical psychology (pp. 239-257). New York, NY: Grune and Stratton.

Hall, C. (1966). The Meaning of Dreams (2nd ed.). New York, NY: McGraw-Hill. (Original work published 1953)

Hall, C. S. (1967). Representation of the laboratory setting in dreams. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease , 144 , 198-206. http://dx.doi.org/10.1097/00005053-196703000-00004

Hall, C. (1991). The two provinces of dreams. Dreaming , 1 , 91-93. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0094320

Hall, C. S., Domhoff, G. W., Blick, K. A., & Weesner, K. E. (1982). The dreams of college men and women in 1950 and 1980: A comparison of dream contents and sex differences. Sleep: Journal of Sleep Research & Sleep Medicine , 5 , 188-194.

Hall, C., & Lind, R. (1970). Dreams, life and literature: A study of Franz Kafka . Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press.

Hall, C., & Nordby, V. (1972). The individual and his dreams . New York, NY: New American Library.

Hall, C., & Nordby, V. (1973). A primer of Jungian psychology . New York, NY: Taplinger.

Hall, C., & Van de Castle, R. (1966). The content analysis of dreams . New York, NY: Appleton-Century- Crofts.

Han, H. (2014). Structural and longitudinal analysis of cognitive social networks in dreams (Unpublished doctoral dissertation). Purdue University, West Lafayette, IN.

Harlow, J., & Roll, S. (1992). Frequency of day residue in dreams of young adults. Perceptual and Motor Skills , 74 , 832-834. http://dx.doi.org/10.2466/pms.1992.74.3.832

Hartmann, E. (1968). The day residue: Time distribution of waking events. Psychophysiology , 5 , 222. Henley-Einion, J., & Blagrove, M. (2014). Assessing the day-residue and dream-lag effects using the identification of multiple correspondences between dream reports and waking life diaries. Dreaming , 24 , 71-88. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0036329

Hoelscher, T., Klinger, E., & Barta, S. (1981). Incorporation of concern- and nonconcern-related verbal stimuli into dream content. Journal of Abnormal Psychology , 90 , 88-91. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0021-843X.90.1.88

Howe, M. (2000). The fate of early memories . Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.

Howe, M. L., & Knott, L. M. (2015). The fallibility of memory in judicial processes: Lessons from the past and their modern consequences. Memory , 23 , 633-656. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09658211.2015.1010709

Hyman, I., & Loftus, E. (2002). False childhood memories and eyewitness memory errors. In M. Eisen & Q. Jodi (Eds.), Memory and suggestibility in the forensic interview (pp. 63-84). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

Johns, M., Coady, M. H., Chan, C. A., Farley, S. M., & Kansagra, S. M. (2013). Evaluating New York City's smoke-free parks and beaches law: A critical multiplist approach to assessing behavioral impact. American Journal of Community Psychology , 51 , 254-263. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10464-012-9519-5

Jung, C. (1963). Memories, dreams, reflections . New York, NY: Pantheon.

Jung, C. (1968). Psychology and alchemy, collected works of C. G. Jung (Vol. 12). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Jung, C. (1974). Dreams . Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Kihlstrom, J. (2002). Demand characteristics in the laboratory and the clinic: Conversations and collaborations with subjects and patients. Prevention & Treatment , 5 . http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/1522-3736.5.1.536c

King, D. B., & DeCicco, T. L. (2009). Dream relevance and the continuity hypothesis: Believe it or not? Dreaming, 19, 207-217. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0017612

Klinger, E. (1971). Structure and functions of fantasy . New York, NY: Wiley-Interscience.

Lakoff, G. (1987). Women, fire, and dangerous things . Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.7208/chicago/9780226471013.001.0001

Loftus, E., Joslyn, S., & Polage, D. (1998). Repression: A mistaken impression? Development and Psychopathology, 10, 781-792. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0954579498001862

Loftus, E., & Ketcham, K. (1994). The myth of repressed memory . New York, NY: St. Martin's Press.

Malinowski, J., & Horton, C. (2011). Themes of continuity. International Journal of Dream Research , 4 , 86-92.

Malinowski, J., & Horton, C. (2014). Evidence for the preferential incorporation of emotional waking-life experiences into dreams. Dreaming , 24 , 18-31. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0036017

Malinowski, J., & Horton, C. (2016, June). Testing the emotion assimilation theory: The effects of emotional intensity and time spent asleep on wake-dream continuity . Paper presented at the International Association for the Study of Dreams 32nd Annual International Conference, Kerkrade, the Netherlands.

Marquardt, C. J. G., Bonato, R. A., & Hoffmann, R. F. (1996). An empirical investigation into the day-residue and dream-lag effects. Dreaming , 6 , 57-65. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0094446

Mattoon, M. (1978). Applied dream analysis: A Jungian approach . New York, NY: Wiley.

Mazzoni, G., & Loftus, E. (1998). Dreaming, believing, and remembering. In J. de Rivera & T. Sarbin (Eds.), Believed-in imaginings: The narrative construction of reality (pp. 145-156). Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/10303-008

Mazzoni, G., Loftus, E., Seitz, A., & Lynn, S. (1999). Changing beliefs and memories through dream interpretation. Applied Cognitive Psychology , 13 , 125-144. http://doi.org/10.1002/(SICI)1099-0720(199904)13:2<125::AID-ACP560>3.0.CO;2-5

Moss, C. S. (1970). Dreams, images, and fantasy: A semantic differential casebook . Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press.

Nielsen, T. (1993). Changes in the kinesthetic content of dreams following somatosensory stimulation of leg muscles during REM sleep. Dreaming , 3 , 99-113. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0094374

Nielsen, T., & Powell, R. (1992). The day-residue and dream-lag effect: A literature review and limited replication of two temporal effects in dream formation. Dreaming , 2 , 67-77. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0094348

Ofshe, R., & Watters, E. (1994). Making monsters: False memories, psychotherapy, and sexual hysteria . New York, NY: Charles Scribner's Sons.

Orne, M. (1962). On the social psychology of the psychological experiment: With particular reference to demand characteristics and their implications. American Psychologist , 17 , 776-783. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0043424

Ornstein, P. A., Ceci, S. J., & Loftus, E. (1998). Adult recollections of childhood abuse: Cognitive and developmental perspectives. Psychology, Public Policy, and Law , 4 , 1025-1051. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/1076-8971.4.4.1025

Pesant, N., & Zadra, A. (2006). Dream content and psychological well-being: A longitudinal study of the continuity hypothesis. Journal of Clinical Psychology , 62 , 111-121. http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/jclp.20212

Reinsel, R., Antrobus, J., & Wollman, M. (1992). Bizarreness in dreams and waking fantasy. In J. S. Antrobus & M. Bertini (Eds.), The neuropsychology of sleep and dreaming (pp. 157-184). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

Revonsuo, A. (2000). The reinterpretation of dreams: An evolutionary hypothesis of the function of dreaming. Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 23 , 877-901. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X00004015

Revonsuo, A., Tuominen, J., & Valli, K. (2015). The avatars in the machine: Dreaming as a simulation of social reality. Open MIND , 32 , 1-28.

Rosenthal, R., & Ambady, N. (1995). Experimenter effects. In A. Manstead & M. Hewstone (Eds.), Encyclopedia of social psychology (pp. 230-235). Oxford, United Kingdom: Blackwell.

Rosenthal, R., & Rosnow, R. (1969). Artifact in behavioral research . New York, NY: Academic Press.

Roussy, F. (1998). Testing the notion of continuity between waking experience and REM dream content (Unpublished Dissertation). University of Ottawa, Ottawa, Ontario, Canada.

Roussy, F., Brunette, M., Mercier, P., Gonthier, I., Grenier, J., Sirois-Berliss, M., . . . Koninck, J. D. (2000). Daily events and dream content: Unsuccessful matching attempts. Dreaming , 10 , 77-83. http://dx.doi.org/10.1023/A:1009496604922

Roussy, F., Camirand, C., Foulkes, D., De Koninck, J., Loftis, M., & Kerr, N. (1996). Does early-night REM dream content reliably reflect presleep state of mind? Dreaming, 6, 121-130. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0094450

Sándor, P., Szakadát, S., & Bódizs, R. (2016). The development of cognitive and emotional processing as reflected in children's dreams: Active self in an eventful dream signals better neuropsychological skills. Dreaming , 26 , 58-78. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/drm0000022

Schredl, M. (2003). Continuity between waking and dreaming: A proposal for a mathematical model. Sleep and Hypnosis , 5 , 26-39.

Schredl, M. (2006). Factors affecting the continuity between waking and dreaming: Emotional intensity and emotional tone of the waking-life event. Sleep and Hypnosis , 8 , 1-5.

Schredl, M. (2008). Dream recall frequency in a representative German sample. Perceptual and Motor Skills , 106 , 699-702. http://dx.doi.org/10.2466/pms.106.3.699-702

Schredl, M. (2012). Continuity in studying the continuity hypothesis of dreaming is needed. International Journal of Dream Research , 5 , 1-8.

Schredl, M., Atanasova, D., Hörmann, K., Maurer, J. T., Hummel, T., & Stuck, B. (2009). Information processing during sleep: The effect of olfactory stimuli on dream content and dream emotions. Journal of Sleep Research , 18 , 285-290. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1365-2869.2009.00737.x

Schredl, M., Desch, S., Röming, F., & Spachmann, A. (2009). Erotic dreams and their relationship to waking-life sexuality. Sexologies , 18 , 38-43. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.sexol.2008.05.001

Schredl, M., & Erlacher, D. (2008). Relation between waking sport activities, reading, and dream content in sport students and psychology students. The Journal of Psychology: Interdisciplinary and Applied , 142 , 267-276. http://dx.doi.org/10.3200/JRLP.142.3.267-276

Schredl, M., Funkhouser, A., & Arn, N. (2005). Dreams of truck drivers: A test of the continuity hypothesis of dreaming. Imagination, Cognition and Personality , 25 , 179-186. http://dx.doi.org/10.2190/578D-MLHA-78R2-HTNW

Schredl, M., Hoffmann, L., Sommer, J. U., & Stuck, B. (2014). Olfactory stimulation during sleep can reactivate odor-associated images. Chemosensory Perception , 7 , 140-146. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s12078-014-9173-4

Schredl, M.,&Hofmann, F. (2003). Continuity between waking activities and dream activities. Consciousness and Cognition: An International Journal , 12 , 298-308. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/S1053-8100(02)00072-7

Schredl, M., & Mathes, J. (2014). Are dreams of killing someone related to waking-life aggression? Dreaming, 24, 176-181. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0037213

Schwartz, R., & Sechrest, L. (2000). Introduction to the classic edition. In E. Webb, D. Campbell, R. Schwartz, & L. Sechrest (Eds.), Unobtrusive measures (2nd ed., pp. xi-xix). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.

Selterman, D., Apetroaia, A., Riela, S., & Aron, A. (2014). Dreaming of you: Behavior and emotion in dreams of significant others predict subsequent relational behavior. Social Psychological and Personality Science , 5 , 111-118. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/1948550613486678

Shaver, P., Schwartz, J., Kirson, D., & O'Connor, C. (1987). Emotion knowledge: Further exploration of a prototype approach. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , 52 , 1061-1086. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.52.6.1061

Stickgold, R. (2003). Human studies of sleep and off-line memory processing. In P. Maquet, C. Smith, & R. Stickgold (Eds.), Sleep and brain plasticity. Oxford Scholarship Online. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198574002.003.0003

Strange, D., Clifasefi, S., & Garry, M. (2007). False memories. In M. Garry & H. Hayne (Eds.), Do justice and let the sky fall: Elizabeth F. Loftus and her contributions to science, law, and academic freedom (pp. 137-168). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

Strauch, I. (2005). REM dreaming in the transition from late childhood to adolescence: A longitudinal study. Dreaming , 15 , 155-169. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/1053-0797.15.3.155

Tamaki, M., Bang, J. W., Watanabe, T., & Sasaki, Y. (2014). The first-night effect suppresses the strength of slow-wave activity originating in the visual areas during sleep. Vision Research , 99 , 154-161. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.visres.2013.10.023

Tamaki, M., Bang, J. W., Watanabe, T., & Sasaki, Y. (2016). Night watch in one brain hemisphere during sleep associated with the first-night effect in humans. Current Biology , 26 , 1190-1194. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.cub.2016.02.063

Tamaki, M., Nittono, H., Hayashi, M., & Hori, T. (2005). Examination of the first-night effect during the sleep-onset period. Sleep: Journal of Sleep Disorders Research , 28 , 195-202.

Uga, V., Lemut, M. C., Zampi, C., Zilli, I., & Salzarulo, P. (2006). Music in dreams. Consciousness and Cognition: An International Journal , 15 , 351-357. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2005.09.003

van Rijn, E., Eichenlaub, J.-B., & Blagrove, M. (2016, June). Incorporating intense emotional events into dreams. Paper presented at the International Association for the Study of Dreams 32nd Annual International Conference, Kerkrade, the Netherlands.

van Rijn, E., Eichenlaub, J.-B., Lewis, P. A., Walker, M. P., Gaskell, M. G., Malinowski, J. E., & Blagrove, M. (2015). The dream-lag effect: Selective processing of personally significant events during rapid eye movement sleep, but not during slow wave sleep. Neurobiology of Learning and Memory , 122 , 98-109. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.nlm.2015.01.009

Vogelsang, L., Anold, S., Schormann, J., Wübbelmann, S., & Schredl, M. (2016). The continuity between waking-life musical activities and music dreams. Dreaming , 26 , 132-141. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/drm0000018

Wamsley, E. J., Tucker, M., Payne, J. D., Benavides, J. A., & Stickgold, R. (2010). Dreaming of a learning task is associated with enhanced sleep-dependent memory consolidation. Current Biology , 20 , 850-855. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.cub.2010.03.027

Webb, E., Campbell, D., Schwartz, R., Sechrest, L., & Grove, J. (1981). Nonreactive measures in the social sciences . Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin.

Whitley, B. E., & Kite, M. E. (2013). Principles of research in behavioral science (3rd ed.). New York, NY: Routledge/Taylor & Francis Group.

Acknowledgements

The author thanks Richard L. Zweigenhaft for his critical reading of the first draft of this article, which led to several changes; to Kelly Bulkeley for very helpful suggestions to make the manuscript more focused; and to David Foulkes for two readings of subsequent drafts of the article, which led to even more changes.

Patrick McNamara Ph.D.

The Continuity Hypothesis of Dreams: A More Balanced Account

Dream elements are both continuous and discontinuous with waking life..

Posted September 10, 2014 | Reviewed by Jessica Schrader

  • Why Is Sleep Important?
  • Find a sleep therapist near me

The continuity hypothesis of dreams suggests that the content of dreams are largely continuous with waking concepts and concerns of the dreamer. In my previous posts on the continuity hypothesis, I have been a bit unfair presenting only a case against the hypothesis and not laying out the facts and arguments that support the hypothesis. So I want to begin to redress that imbalance the best I can in the present post.

Calvin Hall was the first dream researcher to argue that some contents of dreams reflected the daily concerns and ideas of the dreamers rather than the hidden libidinal wishes or compensatory emotional strategies that psychodynamic theorists like Freud and Jung advocated. Through creation of standardized dream content scoring inventories (building on the work of Mary Calkins and others), Hall demonstrated that the most frequently appearing content items of dreams were not bizarre images at all but rather mundane social interactions between the dreamer and people he or she interacted with on a daily basis. One did not need to invoke theories concerning elaborate dreamwork to disguise latent libidinal and aggressive wishes buried in the dream.

Instead simple counts of characters, interactions, objects, actions and events in the dreams could yield a pretty accurate picture of what the dream was about and it wasn’t dramatically different than the daily life of the dreamer. Many dream researchers since Calvin have confirmed that the bread and butter of dreams are the quotidian daily social interactions and concerns most people experience on a daily basis. Domhoff’s (2003) impressive content analyses of a longitudinal dream series collected from a middle aged woman dubbed “Barb Sanders” very convincingly shows that her pattern of aggressive and friendly interactions with key characters in her dreams matched the ups and downs of those same relationships between her and them in waking life.

Thus the empirical support for some degree of continuity between dream content and waking life is strong. The database supporting the theory has been considerably strengthened by many dream researchers over the years since Hall’s pioneering efforts back in the 1950s-1970s. It is therefore clear that any complete theory of dreams must accommodate the data demonstrating substantial continuities between dream content and waking concepts and concerns.

But as every supporter of continuity theory acknowledges there are also dreams that contain some significant discontinuities between dream content and waking concepts/concerns. For example, most people have had dreams that are like long adventure stories or movies. These “narrative-driven” dreams are less quotidian than everyday dreams. They contain more bizarre elements and imagery and have the dreamer engaged in actions and events that are decidedly not like their ordinary ideas, actions and concerns. In addition, there is a significant minority of dream reports that have few or no familiar characters, settings, or activities. Can these sorts of dreams be explained with continuity theory approaches? If attempts are made to do so how can one avoid special pleading, circular reasoning or ad hoc additions to the theory?

What's needed is a theory that accommodates both continuities and discontinuities, but I don't see one of the horizon. In the meantime, one proponent of the continuity hypothesis suggests that building toward such a theory should start with the assumption of continuity, followed by a search for discontinuities that might be of varying types, such as narrative/adventure dreams, unusual elements that reveal figurative thought, and incongruous elements that may reveal that there are cognitive defects of various sorts in dreams (Domhoff, 2007).

Domhoff, G. W. (2003). The scientific study of dreams: Neural networks, cognitive development, and content analysis. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.

Domhoff, G. W. (2007). Realistic simulation and bizarreness in dream content: Past findings and suggestions for future research. In D. Barrett & P. McNamara (Eds.), The new science of dreaming: Content, recall, and personality cor¬relates (Vol. 2, pp. 1-27). Westport, CT: Praeger.

Patrick McNamara Ph.D.

Patrick McNamara, Ph.D. , is Associate Professor of Neurology at Boston University School of Medicine and the author of numerous books and articles on the science of dreams.

  • Find a Therapist
  • Find a Treatment Center
  • Find a Psychiatrist
  • Find a Support Group
  • Find Online Therapy
  • United States
  • Brooklyn, NY
  • Chicago, IL
  • Houston, TX
  • Los Angeles, CA
  • New York, NY
  • Portland, OR
  • San Diego, CA
  • San Francisco, CA
  • Seattle, WA
  • Washington, DC
  • Asperger's
  • Bipolar Disorder
  • Chronic Pain
  • Eating Disorders
  • Passive Aggression
  • Personality
  • Goal Setting
  • Positive Psychology
  • Stopping Smoking
  • Low Sexual Desire
  • Relationships
  • Child Development
  • Self Tests NEW
  • Therapy Center
  • Diagnosis Dictionary
  • Types of Therapy

May 2024 magazine cover

At any moment, someone’s aggravating behavior or our own bad luck can set us off on an emotional spiral that threatens to derail our entire day. Here’s how we can face our triggers with less reactivity so that we can get on with our lives.

  • Emotional Intelligence
  • Gaslighting
  • Affective Forecasting
  • Neuroscience

Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.

To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to  upgrade your browser .

Enter the email address you signed up with and we'll email you a reset link.

  • We're Hiring!
  • Help Center

paper cover thumbnail

The Strong Continuity Hypothesis: Evidence from Arabic-speaking children data

Profile image of Fawaz Qasem

2019, Macrolinguistics

This paper examines the acquisition of subject-verb agreement inflections in the natural speech corpus of two mono-lingual children speaking Yemeni Ibbi Arabic (YIA) between 2 and 3 years old. The two children are Ibrahim and Wala (between the age of 2;1 and 2;10) with Mean Lenghth of Utterance (MLU) range of 2.72 to 3.23 for Ibrahim and 2.9 to 3.27 for Wala. YIA, as a variety of Arabic, has rich and complex morphological system with a fusional type. Verbs are inflected with tense and agreement. Each verbal inflection is marked for person, number, and gender agreement. However, this paper attempts to explore how agreement forms are acquired by YIA-speaking children and examines when YIA children distinguish between first, second, and third person agreement, singular and plural, masculine and feminine agreement forms. The paper argues that agreement inflections (person, number, gender) are available to children early, thereby supporting the Strong Continuity Hypothesis (Lust, 1999). Moreover, the results give evidence to Wexler’s Hypothesis (1998), Very Early Knowledge of Inflection (VEKI), which says that children know the grammatical and phonological properties of inflections in a language in the earliest stages when they enter the two-word stage. Similarly, this study tests Hoekstra and Hyams’ (1995) Early Morpho-syntactic Convergence (EMC) which proposed that children acquire the specifics of inflections of the target language at an early stage.

Related Papers

Arab Journal of Applied Linguistics

Fawaz Qasem

The paper shows that children acquiring Yemeni Ibbi Arabic 4 (henceforth referred to as YIA) go through a stage equivalent to the Root Infinitive (RI) stage found in non-null subject languages in spite of the fact that YIA is a null subject and does not have an infinitive construction. Spontaneous speech of two YIA children (2;1-2;11) showed presence of verbal inflections in 85-90% contexts. However, in a few cases, imperative forms occur in place of tensed forms, and indicate modal irrealis interpretation. We argue that the imperative form is therefore a Root Infinitive Analogue (RIA). The paper also provides evidence for a universal tendency to use non-finite forms in early stages of language development.

strong continuity hypothesis

Ingham of Arabia. C. Holes & R. de Jong (eds). Brill. pp55-73

Bruno Herin , Enam Al-Wer

Ahmad Al-Jallad

Version 2020-1 Updates: 1) chronological divisions - Pre-Historic Old Arabic 2) broken plurals and agreement 3) mythologies of Arabic 4) sound changes, Old Higazi and Tamimi 5) new texts 6) some typos removed, new ones surely generated. I first compiled this manual in 2014 to teach the Historical Grammar of Arabic at the Leiden Linguistics Summer School. I have since continued to update it with new material and insights, and have used various iterations to teach my classes at Leiden University and again at the Leiden Linguistics Summer School, the second time with Dr. Marijn van Putten. The book as it stands now is incomplete; future iterations will cover subjects not treated here, such as the plurals, the morphology of the infinitives and participles, and syntax. The bibliography is not fully formatted and the appendix of texts contains mostly Old Arabic inscriptions but will soon be expanded to include texts from all periods. This text has not been copy edited so please forgive any typos and other infelicities. It is my intention to keep this book open access and free for all to use for research purposes and instruction. Please feel free to cite this text but be sure to include the version number. I will archive the versions at H-Commons so that previous versions are available even though the main text will continue to be updated. Visit my academida.edu (https://leidenuniv.academia.edu/AhmadAlJallad) page to comment a permanent “session”. Users are encouraged to send me suggestions and improvements to better the overall text; I will acknowledge these contributions in the notes. I would like to thank Marijn van Putten for his corrections on this draft while using this manual in his courses and privately.

Evgeniya (Jenia) Gutova

This paper discusses pronominal clitics in Ketama Berber (Western Rif, Morocco). Ketama Berber is usually considered as a variety of Senhaja Berber. It is the westernmost and the most divergent Senhaja variety. The paper is based on fieldwork data collected by the author during several fieldwork trips in 2013-2016 and on Lafkioui 2007. After a general introduction to Ketama Berber (Section 1), its pronominal clitics are discussed (Section 2): clitic pronouns of the direct object (Section 2.1) and of the indirect object (Section 2.2). Special forms of clitic pronouns and their origins are explained. Clitic pronouns in Ketama/Senhaja are compared with Ghomara (based on Mourigh 2015) and Tarifit (based on Lafkioui 2007). Section 3 draws conclusions and summarizes the study.

An introduction to the basic linguistics of Semitic Languages.

Folia Orientalia

David Wilmsen

The negative existential cycle, a typological model that Croft first proposed in 1991, if often acknowledged in the literature, has not been developed until recently. Work with Arabic indicates that it must have operated with an obscure existential particle š , analogous to the more familiar f. One of the characteristics of the cycle is that an erstwhile negative existential, for example miš/muš, can begin to negate verbs in some sub-domains of verbal negation, such, as, for example, futurity. An examination of verbal negation with laysa and its reflexes in the Arabic of classical and pre-classical writing, the vernacular writing from Arabophone Iberia, and a spoken vernacular Arabic of the southern Arabian Peninsula provide evidence that the negative existential cycle has operated upon reflexes of laysa.

Journal of Language Contact 6 (2013) 358–378

Paul-Alain Beaulieu

kamal hasan

Fiddler On the Roof

Loading Preview

Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.

RELATED PAPERS

Hebrew Studies 54, pp. 387-410

Na'ama Pat-El , Aren M . Wilson-Wright

Abel Covarrubias

Aaron Rubin

Robert Murphy

kirk miller

Journal of Semitic Studies 60

Fred Putnam

Encyclopedia of Arabic Language and Linguistics, ed. Kees Versteegh. Leiden: Brill. 3.408–22

John Huehnergard

BO Isaksson

Ayoub Loutfi

Robert Holmstedt

Raina Heaton , Patricia Anderson

Assaf Bar-Moshe

Supplement to the Proceedings of the Seminar for Arabian Studies 44

Sergey Loesov , Moscow Circle for Aramaic Studies

marwa BADRANE

Daniel Wilson

Journal of Afroasiatic Languages

Girma A Demeke

saleh shaalan

Romano - Arabica , Gabriel Biţună , George Grigore , Laura Sitaru

Mediterranean Language Review

Bruno Herin

Lameen Souag

Sam AlIraqi

Dola Algady

Geoffrey Khan

Mid-America Journal of Theology

R. Andrew Compton

Shayna Gardiner

Craig S Petrovich

Bulletin of the Faculty of Arts, Assiut University, vol. 26

Mohamed Mansour

Julien Dufour

Darien Hernández

Lily Okalani Kahn

Ancient Near Eastern Studies

RELATED TOPICS

  •   We're Hiring!
  •   Help Center
  • Find new research papers in:
  • Health Sciences
  • Earth Sciences
  • Cognitive Science
  • Mathematics
  • Computer Science
  • Academia ©2024

The Continuity Hypothesis

Cite this chapter.

strong continuity hypothesis

  • William N. Morris 2  

Part of the book series: Springer Series in Social Psychology ((SSSOC))

172 Accesses

The idea that everyday good and bad moods might differ from clinically significant depression and mania only in terms of degree rather than kind suggests that these states are on continua such that intensification of normal processes can produce disorder. This view, sometimes referred to as the continuity hypothesis (e.g., see Beck, 1967; Blatt et al., 1976; Coyne, 1986; Depue et al., 1981; Eastwood et al., 1985; Gotlib, 1984), is a controversial one that has tended to divide clinicians and researchers into two camps. Opposed to the continuity hypothesis are those who take a biomedical orientation toward affective disorder, regarding it as a disease traceable to abnormal neurophysiological and biochemical processes (e.g., Whybrow & Mendels, 1969; Siever & Davis, 1985). In support of the hypothesis, one finds an uneasy alliance of behaviorally, cognitively, and psychoanalytically oriented psychologists and psychiatrists who believe that psychological processes and vulnerabilities are sufficient to explain clinically significant depression. At stake are the implications of the continuity hypothesis: that we can learn more about the nature of affective disorder through “analog” research, that is, by studying the moods of “normal” individuals, and that psychological therapies can be effective remedies, especially to the extent that they are based on evidence about ways to successfully eliminate everyday bad moods.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Unable to display preview.  Download preview PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

strong continuity hypothesis

Mood Disturbances

strong continuity hypothesis

Affect, Mood, Emotions: Depressive Disorders and Bipolar and Related Disorders

strong continuity hypothesis

Adaptation and Psychological Disorders

Author information, authors and affiliations.

Department of Psychology, Dartmouth College, 03755, Hanover, New Hampshire, USA

William N. Morris

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1989 Springer-Verlag New York Inc.

About this chapter

Morris, W.N. (1989). The Continuity Hypothesis. In: Mood. Springer Series in Social Psychology. Springer, New York, NY. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4612-3648-1_7

Download citation

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4612-3648-1_7

Publisher Name : Springer, New York, NY

Print ISBN : 978-1-4612-8190-0

Online ISBN : 978-1-4612-3648-1

eBook Packages : Springer Book Archive

Share this chapter

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Publish with us

Policies and ethics

  • Find a journal
  • Track your research

Keith E Rice's Integrated SocioPsychology Blog & Pages

Keith E Rice's Integrated SocioPsychology Blog & Pages

Aligning, integrating and applying the behavioural sciences

Home » Lifespan » Continuity Hypothesis

Continuity Hypothesis

Updated: 24 August 2019

The Continuity Hypothesis was put forward by John Bowlby (1953) as a critical effect of attachments in his development of Attachment Theory . He was greatly influenced by Sigmund Freud (1940) who viewed an infant’s first relationship – usually with the mother – as  “t he prototype of all later love-relations” . This ‘prototype’ Bowlby termed the internal working model – a set of conscious and/or unconscious  rules and expectations which will be applied to all  relationships we develop with others. So our first experiences will influence our expectations and actions in future experiences – hence the sense of continuity. In his concept of the internal working model, Bowlby was borrowing Kenneth Craik’s (1943) concept of ‘mental models’ – ie: that all humans carry in their heads mental representations of the external world and their relations with it. These mental models – schemas and complexes of schemas in the selfplex – then provide the basis on which the individual perceives and deals with the external world. According to Bowlby, with the aid of working models, children predict the attachment figure’s likely behaviour and plan their own responses. What type of model they construct is therefore of great consequence.

How the internal working model formed will influence the formation of and engagement in future relationships is the basis of the  Continuity Hypothesis .

Childhood relationships Alan Sroufe’s  reports from the Minnesota Longitudinal Study (MLS) have shown strong support for the playing out of the internal working model in children’s later relationships. In the MLS a cohort of children were followed from  the age of 12 months to adolescence and beyond.  Throughout the children were rated by  teachers, trained observers and camp  counsellors at special events arranged  for the children. Those rated as securely attached in infancy (using the Strange Situation ) were also rated  later as being more  popular, having more  initiative, more  empathy and being higher in social  competency, self-confidence and self-esteem  ( Alan Sroufe et al , 1999). In Gravesian terms, this can be seen as the PURPLE vMEME , having its safety-in-belonging needs met, facilitates the development of healthy RED. On the other hand findings that insecure-avoidant children are most likely to have low social status ( Peter LaFreniere & Alan Sroufe , 1985) and most likely to be bullied, with insecure-resistants doing most of the bullying ( Michael T roy & Alan  Sroufe , 1987), suggest that failure to meet PURPLE’s safety-in-belonging needs may lead to unhealthy forms of RED emerging.

Karlen Lyons-Ruth, Lisbeth Alpern & Betty Repacholi’s  (1990) longitudinal study is one of the few to have also used Mary Main & Judith Solomon’s (1990) additional Strange Situation classification of Type D: disorganised. They found that infant attachment type at 18 months is one of the best predictors of problematic relationships at 5, with Type Ds struggling the most to form friendships.

Not all research strongly supports the Continuity Hypothesis , though.   Mary Main & Donna Weston (1981) found only low correlations between the child’s attachment type and the child’s various relationships.

Interestingly, Inge Bretherton et al (1989) have suggested that  children may develop several internal working models that help them make sense of their different social roles (son or daughter, sibling, cousin, friend, etc). Given what we now understand about the the formation of schemas, the concept of multiple internal working models may help explain  Nick Fox, H Joesbury & D R Hannay’s 1991 observation that the attachment type an infant displays with one parent may not be a reliable indicator for the attachment type the child displays with the other parent.

Manuela Verissimo et al (2011)  carried out a prospective study in which they assessed the attachment types of 35 children aged between 29 and 38 months from 2-parent families, using separate observations for each parent in the child’s home. Not only did they find some children displayed a different attachment type with each parent but that secure attachment with the father correlated strongly with the number of reciprocated friendships in nursery at the age of 4 years-old. Paradoxically the quality of the child’s relationship with the mother did not impact on nursery friendships. Not only does this finding seem to contradict Bowlby’s emphasis on monotropy  but it offers support to both the concept of the Continuity Hypothesis and the idea of multiple internal working models.

Carollee Howes, Catherine Matheson & Claire Hamilton (1994) state that there is not always a positive correlation between parent-child & later child-peer relationships. Even if there is a correlation, there may well  be other ways of explaining it than the inner working model concept – eg: some children may simply be better at  forming relationships.

Adolescent Relationships Cynthia Wilson Moore (1997) measured the attachment style of 100 14-15 -year-olds using an interview process and asked a close friend of each teenager to rate their behaviour for social acceptability. What Moore found was that secure teens were less likely to engage in risky sexual activities – eg: unsafe sex – than their insecure peers but were more likely to have had sex. She concluded from this research that having a secure attachment type better prepares an adolescent for entering the world of adult sexual relationships. Having positive self-esteem would enable RED to stand up for itself with a strong internal locus of control and enter the adult world more on its own terms. Having low self-esteem may drive an unhealthy vMEME harmonic of RED engaging in risky behaviours to get acceptance for PURPLE’s belongingness needs.

Again, though, not all research shows continuity. In a longitudinal study Peter Zimmermann et al (2000) reassessed via interviews 44 16-year-olds who had originally gone through the Strange Situation between 12-18 months. They found that infant attachment type was not a good predictor of attachments in adolescence, with negatively-impacting life events seeming to have altered secure attachments to an insecure type.

Love Quiz Romantic/sexual relationships are a key area of research in evaluating the Continuity Hypothesis . One of the most famous studies into the lasting effects of infant attachment on adult relationships is the ‘Love Quiz’ by  Cindy Hazan & Phil Shaver ( 1987).

The researchers  wanted to see if there was a correlation between the infant’s attachment type and their future approach to romantic relationships. They used a survey, presented as a ‘love quiz’ which  consisted of 2 components:-

  • A measure of attachment type – a simple adjective checklist of childhood relationships with parents and parents’ relationships with each other
  • A love experience questionnaire which assessed individual’s beliefs about romantic love – eg: whether it lasted forever, whether it could be found easily, how much trust there was in a romantic relationship – and asked about issues such as fear of closeness, jealousy and obsessive preoccupation

The Love Quiz was printed in local newspaper the Rocky Mountain News and readers were asked to send in their responses.  Hazan & Shaver analysed the first 620 replies sent in from people aged from 14 to 82. 205 were from men and 415 from women. 42% of participants were married and 31% were dating. The researchers classified the respondents’ according to Mary Ainsworth’s Strange Situation  infant attachment types of secure , insecure – resistant and insecure – avoidant and looked for corresponding adult love styles – viz:-

  • Secure types described their love experiences as happy, friendly and trusting – emphasising being able to accept their partner regardless of their faults – with such relationships tending to be more enduring, with the initial passion reappearing from time to time and for some ‘romantic love’ never fading. They were happy depending on others and comfortable if others are dependent on them. They were happy to be close to others.
  • Insecure- resistant types experienced love as involving obsession, a desire for reciprocation, emotional highs and lows, extreme sexual attraction and jealousy, and worry that their partners didn’t really love them or might abandon them. Their desire for intense closeness could frighten others away.
  • Insecure- avoidant types typically feared intimacy, emotional highs and lows, and jealousy and believed they did not need love to be happy. They were uncomfortable being close to and/or depending on others.

From the sample, 56% were classified as secure, 25% avoidant and 19% resistant. These are very similar to the proportions of secure/insecure infants in the classic studies by Ainsworth  – supporting the researchers’ hypothesis. Hazan & Shaver concluded that there was evidence to support the concept of the inner working model having a life- long effect. However, they did concede that not everyone stayed true to their infant attachment style and that some people did change as they grew older.

There are issues with Hazan & Shaver’s methodology. The respondents were self- reporting – and people do not always give truthful answers. Plus,  people were recording their memories of infant experience and such memories may not always be accurate. Additionally, the respondents were self- selecting and, therefore, the results may be subject to volunteer bias . – ie: certain types of personality are more likely to self-select for this kind of investigation and, therefore, they may not be representative of everyone.

Hazan & Shaver repeated the Love Quiz in 1993 and again found strong evidence for a correlation between infant attachment type and adult love style – though the correlation was not quite as strong this time. (In total the 2  Love Quiz studies involved 1200 participants.)

It is important to bear in mind that Hazan & Shaver only established a correlation . Therefore, cause- and- effect cannot be assumed from their work.

Other research on romantic relationships A number of studies have supported the Love Quiz findings – eg: Judith Feeney & Patricia Noller (1990) found that securely- attached individuals had the most long- term enduring romantic relationships while insecure- avoidant types had the most short- lived and least- intense relationships. In 1992 Feeney & Noller reported that avoidant attachment types amongst 193 university students were more likely to have their relationships fail. The researchers also found that some attachment types changed when the relationships went from casual to committed. Like Hazen & Shaver, Feeney & Noller show that attachment types aren’t necessarily totally fixed.

In a 4- month study of heterosexual relationships among Canadian undergraduates Patrick Keelan, Karen Dion & Kenneth Dion (1994) found that those with a secure attachment style expressed more satisfaction with and greater commitment to the relationship and trusted their partner more.

Interestingly Kelly Brennan & Phil Shaver (1995) found that, among undergraduates involved in a romantic relationship, there is also a weak but significant tendency to be attracted to someone with a similar attachment style.

Gerard McCarthy’s (1999) study of women whose attachment types had been recorded in infancy can be considered longitudinal. He found:-

  • Insecure- avoidant infants grew up to have the most difficulty in romantic relationships
  • Insecure- resistant infants grew up to have the poorest relationships
  • Securely- attached infants grew up to have the most successful romantic relationships and friendships

These findings could be predicted from the Continuity Hypothesis  – as could Everett Waters et al’s (2000) longitudinal study of 50 middle class white infants which found that 70% of their sample, assessed through interviews as young adults, received the same secure, resistant or avoidant classification as originally designated via the Strange Situation at the age of 12 months. Those who had changed attachment style had experienced a negatively-impacting life event such as parental divorce or parental death/life-threatening illness. This last point reflects the findings of Zimmermann et al.

Adult Attachment Measures A transgenerational effect has been shown by Susan Sprecher, Rodney Cate & Lauren Levin (1998). They compared the love styles of 2 sets of students, one whose parents were divorced and one whose parents had stayed together. This second group was then divided into those whose parents had happy marriages and those who didn’t. Amongst the females with divorced parents and unhappily married parents, they were more likely to have an avoidant attachment style and less likely to have a secure one. In terms of John Lee’s  (1973) love styles – see What is Love? – they were less likely to be Pragma, Agape or Mania and generally had a less idealistic view of romantic love. Male participants whose parents were divorced were more likely to show Eros as their preferred love style – this tendency was even stronger amongst men whose parents were unhappily married.

The transgenerational effect reflects the power of the parents’ memes to embed into their children’s schemas.

Heidi Bailey et al (2007) were able to catch this transgenerational in vivo, as it were. They observed babies using the Strange Situation and then interviewed their mothers via the Adult Attachment Interview (AAI) . What they found was that those who reported poor attachments to their own parents were more likely to have poorly-attached children themselves. Bailey et al fit with the earlier findings of David Quinton & Michael Rutter (1984) who found that women raised in institutions were generally less sensitive, warm and supportive of their own children than a control group . However, Quinton & Rutter did not seek to imply cause-and-effect as they identified other variables such as teenage pregnancy and having an unsupportive partner. They also acknowledged that some of the women raised in institutions were, in fact, very sensitive mothers.

The AAI  has proved a critical step forward in assessing transgenerational effects of internal working models and investigating how changes in attachment types take place.

Developed by Carol George, Nancy Kaplan & Mary Main (1984), this semi-structured interview taps into adult representation of attachment (ie: internal working models) by assessing general and specific recollections from the participants’ childhood. The interview is coded based on quality of discourse (especially coherence) and content. Categories are designed to predict parental stances.

Parental Adult Attachment status includes:-

  • Autonomous : they value attachment relationships, describe them in a balanced way and as influential – their discourse is coherent, internally consistent, and non-defensive in nature
  • Dismissing : they show memory lapses, minimise negative aspects of their childhood and deny personal impact on relationships. Their positive descriptions are often contradicted or unsupported and the discourse is defensive
  • Preoccupied/Entangled : they experience continuing preoccupation with their own parents and their discourse is incoherent. They have angry or ambivalent representations of the past.
  • Unresolved/Disorganised : they show trauma resulting from unresolved loss or abuse

Some of the strongest external validation of the AAI involves its demonstrated ability to predict people‘s children’s classifications in the Strange Situation .  Mary Main & Ruth Goldwyn (1994) found a link between early attachment type and adult relationship pattern. Dismissing is associated with insecure-avoidant, autonomous with secure and  preoccupied with with insecure-resistant. Building on these associations,  Joan Vondra, Daniel Shaw & M Cristina Kevenides (1995) found dismissing mothers were controlling with avoidant children, autonmous were sensitive with secure children and preoccupied mothers tended to be unresponsive with avoidant children.

Evaluation of the Continuity Hypothesis Research seems to indicate indicate that the   majority of people tend to display a relatively-similar attachment style throughout their lives and this reflects the importance of nurturing the PURPLE vMEME from the start of life. However, maintaining a similar attachment style is far from universal As Zimmerman et al and Waters et al show, negative life events during childhood and adolescence can have a destabilising effect, with the internal working model(s) shifting to a less secure pattern of schemas in the selfplex.

A longitudinal meta-analysis by William Chopik, Robin Edelstein & Kevin Grimm (2019) indicates that the intensity of resistance – Chopik, Edelstein & Grimm refer to this as ‘anxious attachment’ – and avoidance may vary over a lifetime.  These insecure thoughts and behaviours are likely to reach a peak during adolescence due to the stress of transitioning from the primary belonging relationship with parents to new belongings with peers and first romantic relationships. Resistance and avoidance tend to decline in full adulthood when people are often settled into more secure and stable relationships. They are usually at their lowest in later life – “declines in anxiety and avoidance may reflect the efforts of older adults to become closer to their close friends and family.”

These developmental changes can be seen as reflecting the stability of the PURPLE vMEME. The adolescent transition to new relationships is a disturbing time for PURPLE which may account in part at least for such powerful assertions of RED for many in the mid-teens and early adulthood. Settling down with a family and building closer relationships in later life all help satisfy PURPLE’s need for safety-in-belonging.

What has been relatively unexplored in Attachment Theory is the impact an adult romantic partner has on the attachment type. As a partner can be incredibly influential in someone’s life,  Kim Bartholome & Leonard Horowitz (1991) argue that can change someone’s attachment style – for better or for worse.

strong continuity hypothesis

Borrowing from the AAI , Bartholomew & Horowitz  present a model that identifies 4 categories or styles of adult attachment. Their model is based on the idea that adult attachment styles reflect people’s thoughts about both themselves –  Bowlby’s concept of the internal working model – and their partner. Specifically, attachment styles depend on whether or not people judge their partners to be generally accessible and responsive to requests for support, and whether or not people judge themselves to be the kind of individuals towards which others want to respond and lend help. The researchers propose 4 categories based on positive or negative thoughts about partners and on positive or negative thoughts about self – see graphic above.

strong continuity hypothesis

Bartholomew & Horowitz devised both interview and self-report measures of the 4 styles and what they see as the 2 dimensions – avoidance and anxiety – that organise them conceptually. See graphic above. This approach helps to explain how some people are very different in adult relationships to how they were as children.  Michael Rutter, David Quinton & Jonathan Hill  (1999), who found that people who had had problematic relationships with their parents, could go on to achieve secure, stable and happy adult relationships. They termed these relationships ‘earned security’. Their terminology again indicates that central to security in all relationships is the health of the PURPLE vMEME.

An alternative explanation for this apparent continuity, where there appears to be continuity, lies in Jerome Kagan’s Temperament Hypothesis (1984). Kagan notes that innate temperamental characteristics which make infants ‘easy’ or ‘difficult’ have a serious impact on the quality of the mother- infant relationship and thus the attachment type. Although they can be modified by epigenetics , these innate temperamental characteristics usually influence the individual throughout life and thus adult love relationships.

 Joseph Jacobson & Diane Wille (1986) postulate that a child’s temperament may influence the formation of relationships. They state that children who are appealing to their parents  are likely to be appealing to others. So that a child who does well in one relationship is  likely to do well in others.

So temperament, life events and previous romantic experiences may all strongly influence an attachment as well as the individual’s internal working model(s). Moreover, the recent research of Chopik, Edelstein & Grimm may predicate a sift in the concept of attachment – from ‘types’ more to ‘tendencies’.

POST A COMMENT

You can use these tags: <a href="" title=""> <abbr title=""> <acronym title=""> <b> <blockquote cite=""> <cite> <code> <del datetime=""> <em> <i> <q cite=""> <s> <strike> <strong>

One Response

' src=

Even though secure attachments as infants provides for more security in romantic relationships in years to come, it is true that different traumas can enter in and hijack the original secure attachment. The more parents can provide and maintain family stability, the better off their children will fare in their own relationships.

Thank you for visiting nature.com. You are using a browser version with limited support for CSS. To obtain the best experience, we recommend you use a more up to date browser (or turn off compatibility mode in Internet Explorer). In the meantime, to ensure continued support, we are displaying the site without styles and JavaScript.

  • View all journals
  • Explore content
  • About the journal
  • Publish with us
  • Sign up for alerts
  • Published: 19 June 2024

Timeliness criticality in complex systems

  • José Moran   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0001-5253-9831 1 , 2 ,
  • Matthijs Romeijnders   ORCID: orcid.org/0009-0000-3605-3807 3 ,
  • Pierre Le Doussal 4 ,
  • Frank P. Pijpers   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0001-7572-9435 5 , 6 ,
  • Utz Weitzel 7 , 8 , 9 ,
  • Debabrata Panja   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0003-2141-9735 3 , 10 &
  • Jean-Philippe Bouchaud 11 , 12  

Nature Physics ( 2024 ) Cite this article

1110 Accesses

1 Citations

15 Altmetric

Metrics details

  • Applied mathematics
  • Complex networks
  • Nonlinear phenomena
  • Phase transitions and critical phenomena

In complex systems, external parameters often determine the phase in which the system operates, that is, its macroscopic behaviour. For nearly a century, statistical physics has been used to extensively study systems’ transitions across phases, (universal) critical exponents and related dynamical properties. Here we consider the functionality of systems, particularly operations in socio-technical ones, production in economic ones and, more generally, any schedule-based system, where timing is of crucial importance. We introduce a stylized model of delay propagation on temporal networks, where the magnitude of the delay-mitigating buffer acts as a control parameter. The model exhibits timeliness criticality, a novel form of critical behaviour. We characterize fluctuations near criticality, commonly referred to as avalanches, and identify the corresponding critical exponents. The model exhibits timeliness criticality also when run on real-world temporal systems such as production networks. Additionally, we explore potential connections with the mode-coupling theory of glasses, depinning transition and directed polymer problem.

This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution

Access options

Access Nature and 54 other Nature Portfolio journals

Get Nature+, our best-value online-access subscription

24,99 € / 30 days

cancel any time

Subscribe to this journal

Receive 12 print issues and online access

195,33 € per year

only 16,28 € per issue

Buy this article

  • Purchase on Springer Link
  • Instant access to full article PDF

Prices may be subject to local taxes which are calculated during checkout

strong continuity hypothesis

Similar content being viewed by others

strong continuity hypothesis

Multi pathways temporal distance unravels the hidden geometry of network-driven processes

strong continuity hypothesis

Dynamics of cascades on burstiness-controlled temporal networks

strong continuity hypothesis

Nonequilibrium thermodynamics of the asymmetric Sherrington-Kirkpatrick model

Data availability.

The source data for all figures in the paper (including Supplementary Figs. 1 – 6 ) are linked from the ‘Data and codes for figures’ section in the Supplementary Information to the respective folders in the GitHub repository ( https://github.com/jose-moran/timeliness_criticality/tree/main/figures/ ).

Code availability

The codes used to generate all the figures in the paper (including Supplementary Figs. 1 – 6 ) are linked from the ‘Data and codes for figures’ section in the Supplementary Information to the respective folders in the GitHub repository ( https://github.com/jose-moran/timeliness_criticality/tree/main/figures/ ).

Moran, J., Pijpers, F. P., Weitzel, U., Bouchaud, J.-P. & Panja, D. Temporal criticality in socio-technical systems. Preprint at https://arxiv.org/abs/2307.03546 (2023).

Dekker, M. M. & Panja, D. Cascading dominates large-scale disruptions in transport over complex networks. PLoS ONE 16 , e0246077 (2021).

Article   Google Scholar  

Giannikas, V. et al. A data-driven method to assess the causes and impact of delay propagation in air transportation systems. Transp. Res. Part C: Emerg. Technol. 143 , 103862 (2022).

Ledwoch, A., Brintrup, A., Mehnen, J. örn & Tiwari, A. Systemic risk assessment in complex supply networks. IEEE Syst. J. 12 , 1826–1837 (2016).

Article   ADS   Google Scholar  

Brintrup, A. & Ledwoch, A. Supply network science: emergence of a new perspective on a classical field. Chaos 28 , 033120 (2018).

Article   ADS   MathSciNet   Google Scholar  

Colon, C. élian & Ghil, M. Economic networks: heterogeneity-induced vulnerability and loss of synchronization. Chaos 27 , 126703 (2017).

The Associated Press. Ship still stuck in Suez Canal as backlog grows to 150 other ships. CBC (25 March 2021).

Colon, C., Hallegatte, S. & Rozenberg, J. Criticality analysis of a country’s transport network via an agent-based supply chain model. Nat. Sustain. 4 , 209–215 (2020).

Kosasih, E. E. & Brintrup, A. Reinforcement learning provides a flexible approach for realistic supply chain safety stock optimisation. IFAC-PapersOnLine 55 , 1539–1544 (2022).

Dessertaine, T., Moran, J., Benzaquen, M. & Bouchaud, J.-P. Out-of-equilibrium dynamics and excess volatility in firm networks. J. Econ. Dyn. Control 138 , 104362 (2022).

Article   MathSciNet   Google Scholar  

Munoz, M. A. & Hwa, T. On nonlinear diffusion with multiplicative noise. Europhys. Lett. 41 , 147 (1998).

Hinrichsen, H. Non-equilibrium critical phenomena and phase transitions into absorbing states. Adv. Phys. 49 , 815–958 (2000).

Götze, W. Complex Dynamics of Glass-Forming Liquids: A Mode-Coupling Theory Vol. 143 (Oxford Univ. Press, 2009).

Holme, P. & Saramäki, J. Temporal networks. Phys. Rep. 519 ., 97–125 (2012).

Holme, P. and Saramäki, J. Temporal Networks (SpringerLink, 2013).

Sellitto, M., Biroli, G. & Toninelli, C. Facilitated spin models on Bethe lattice: bootstrap percolation, mode-coupling transition and glassy dynamics. Europhys. Lett. 69 , 496 (2005).

Rosso, A., Le Doussal, P. & Wiese, K. J. Avalanche-size distribution at the depinning transition: a numerical test of the theory. Phys. Rev. B 80 , 144204 (2009).

Bouchaud, E. Scaling properties of cracks. J. Phys.: Condens. Matter 9 , 4319 (1997).

ADS   Google Scholar  

Lin, J., Lerner, E., Rosso, A. & Wyart, M. Scaling description of the yielding transition in soft amorphous solids at zero temperature. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 111 , 14382–14387 (2014).

Ponson, L. & Pindra, N. Crack propagation through disordered materials as a depinning transition: a critical test of the theory. Phys. Rev. E 95 , 053004 (2017).

Newman, M. E. J. & Barkema, G. T. Monte Carlo Methods in Statistical Physics (Oxford Univ. Press, 1999).

Mastrandrea, R., Fournet, J. & Barrat, A. Contact patterns in a high school: a comparison between data collected using wearable sensors, contact diaries and friendship surveys. PLoS ONE 10 , e0136497 (2015).

Génois, M. et al. Data on face-to-face contacts in an office building suggest a low-cost vaccination strategy based on community linkers. Network Sci. 3 , 326–347 (2015).

Dekker, M. M., Schram, R. D., Ou, J. & Panja, D. Hidden dependence of spreading vulnerability on topological complexity. Phys. Rev. E 105 , 054301 (2022).

Dekker, M. M. et al. Quantifying agent impacts on contact sequences in social interactions. Sci. Rep. 12 , 3483 (2022).

Roux, S. & Herrmann, H. J. Disorder induced nonlinear conductivity. Europhys. Lett. 4 , 1227 (1987).

Wichmann, P., Brintrup, A., Baker, S., Woodall, P. & McFarlane, D. Towards automatically generating supply chain maps from natural language text. IFAC-PapersOnLine 51 , 1726–1731 (2018).

Sterman, J. Modeling managerial behavior: misperceptions of feedback in a dynamic decision making experiment. Manage. Sci. 35 , 321–339 (1989).

Dekker, M. M. et al. A next step in disruption management: combining operations research and complexity science. Public Transp. 14 , 5–26 (2021).

Shughrue, C., Werner, B. & Seto, K. C. Global spread of local cyclone damages through urban trade networks. Nat. Sustain. 3 , 606–613 (2020).

Bak, P., Chen, K., Scheinkman, J. & Woodford, M. Aggregate fluctuations from independent sectoral shocks: self-organized criticality in a model of production and inventory dynamics. Ric. Econ. 47 , 3–30 (1993).

Moran, J. & Bouchaud, J.-P. May’s instability in large economies. Phys. Rev. E 100 , 032307 (2019).

Bernanke, B. S., Gertler, M. & Gilchrist, S. The financial accelerator and the flight to quality. Rev. Econ. Stat. 78 , 1–15 (1996).

Bernanke, B. S., Geithner, T. F. & Paulson Jr, H. M. Firefighting: The Financial Crisis and Its Lessons (Penguin, 2019).

Gabaix, X. The granular origins of aggregate fluctuations. Econometrica 79 , 733–772 (2011).

Carvalho, V. M. & Tahbaz, A. Production networks: a primer. Annu. Rev. Econ. 11 , 635–663 (2019).

Pichler, A. & Farmer, J. D. Simultaneous supply and demand constraints in input–output networks: the case of COVID-19 in Germany, Italy, and Spain. Econ. Syst. Res. 34 , 273–293 (2021).

Lafrogne-Joussier, R., Martin, J. & Mejean, I. Supply shocks in supply chains: evidence from the early lockdown in China. IMF Econ. Rev. 71 , 170–215 (2022).

Pichler, A. & Diem, C. et al. Building an alliance to map global supply networks. Science 382 , 270–272 (2023).

Download references

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

Mathematical Institute and Institute for New Economic Thinking at the Oxford Martin School, University of Oxford, Oxford, UK

Complexity Science Hub, Vienna, Austria

Department of Information and Computing Sciences, Utrecht University, Utrecht, The Netherlands

Matthijs Romeijnders & Debabrata Panja

Laboratoire de Physique de l’École Normale Supérieure, ENS, Université PSL, CNRS, Sorbonne Université, Université de Paris, Paris, France

Pierre Le Doussal

Statistics Netherlands, The Hague, Netherlands

Frank P. Pijpers

Korteweg-de Vries Institute for Mathematics, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam, The Netherlands

School of Business and Economics, Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam, Amsterdam, The Netherlands

Utz Weitzel

Tinbergen Institute, Amsterdam, The Netherlands

Nijmegen School of Management, Radboud University, Nijmegen, The Netherlands

Centre for Complex Systems Studies, Utrecht University, Utrecht, The Netherlands

Debabrata Panja

Capital Fund Management, Paris, France

Jean-Philippe Bouchaud

X-CFM Chair of EconophysiX, École Polytechnique, Palaiseau, France

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Contributions

J.-P.B. and D.P. conceptualized the timeliness criticality. J.-P.B., P.L.D., J.M., D.P., F.P.P. and M.R. analysed the timeliness criticality. All authors contributed to the paper.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Debabrata Panja .

Ethics declarations

Competing interests.

The authors declare no competing interests.

Peer review

Peer review information.

Nature Physics thanks Yuichi Ikeda and Jari Saramäki for their contribution to the peer review of this work.

Additional information

Publisher’s note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Extended data

Extended data fig. 1 an example of how an avalanche is defined..

The mean delay per node for the mean-field case is plotted (blue), along with an orange line corresponding to mean delay equals B (see text for the parameter values used for this plot). For the avalanche shown, we define t start  = 4, 760, 908 as the time when the mean delay per node exceeds B , and t end  = 4, 785, 490 as the time when for the first time after t start the mean delay per node falls below B again. Then the mean delay per node in the interval \(\left[{t}_{{{{\rm{start}}}}},{t}_{{{{\rm{end}}}}}\right)\) constitutes a delay avalanche, from which the persistence time and the size of the avalanche are obtained respectively as t p  =  t end  −  t start  = 24, 582, and as the area between the blue curve and the orange line over the interval \(\left[{t}_{{{{\rm{start}}}}},{t}_{{{{\rm{end}}}}}\right)\) .

Supplementary information

Supplementary information.

Supplementary Sections A–E, Figs. 1–6 and Tables 1 and 2.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article.

Moran, J., Romeijnders, M., Doussal, P.L. et al. Timeliness criticality in complex systems. Nat. Phys. (2024). https://doi.org/10.1038/s41567-024-02525-w

Download citation

Received : 06 November 2023

Accepted : 25 April 2024

Published : 19 June 2024

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1038/s41567-024-02525-w

Share this article

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

This article is cited by

Critical delay accumulation.

  • Jari Saramäki

Nature Physics (2024)

Quick links

  • Explore articles by subject
  • Guide to authors
  • Editorial policies

Sign up for the Nature Briefing: AI and Robotics newsletter — what matters in AI and robotics research, free to your inbox weekly.

strong continuity hypothesis

IMAGES

  1. PPT

    strong continuity hypothesis

  2. How to Write Hypothesis

    strong continuity hypothesis

  3. How to Write a Strong Hypothesis in 6 Simple Steps

    strong continuity hypothesis

  4. Attachment Theory: The Continuity Hypothesis

    strong continuity hypothesis

  5. PPT

    strong continuity hypothesis

  6. Continuity Principle (Gestalt Theory)

    strong continuity hypothesis

VIDEO

  1. Strong continuity of representation of L^\infty

  2. Continuity Testing

  3. Continuity Example

  4. Do you know about the pre-cooling process in chicken meat processing?

  5. Continuity :Cauchy's and Heine's Definition, RHL=LHL= f(x) (Examples)

  6. Correlation (Parametric and Non-parametric) with hypothesis in SPSS in Bangla

COMMENTS

  1. Universal grammar: The strong continuity hypothesis in first language

    Introduces the theory of universal grammar (UG) as a model of the initial state, fundamental to the explanation of 1st language acquisition and briefly reviews a history of supporting evidence for UG that has accrued over the past several decades. Then an indeterminacy is identified in the interpretation of UG, which characterizes work in the field today. Outlines of a solution to this ...

  2. Universal Grammar and critical periods: A most amusing paradox

    Epstein, S. D., Flynn, S. & Martohardjono, G. (1993 c) The strong continuity hypothesis in adult L2 acquisition of functional categories. Paper presented at Workshop on Recent Advances in Generative Approaches to Second Language Acquisition, Massachusetts Institute of Technology , 01 , 1993 .

  3. Continuity and Modularity in Language Acquisition and Research

    Continuity. was coined first by Macnamara (1982) and elaborated in Pinker (1984), it has since been emphasized in most work in the generative tradition (Lust, 1999; Wexler, 1999). This quote is representative, referring to the Strong Continuity hypothesis: "UG (where this term refers to the "principles and parameters" which provide the

  4. The Strong Continuity Hypothesis: Some Evidence Concerning Functional

    This chapter discusses functional categories in L2 acquisition. For language acquisition research driven by current linguistic theory, one crucial problem, perhaps the most crucial, is the availability of universal grammar (UG) to the learner or acquirer. For many first language (L1) researchers who accept generative theory in its varying ...

  5. PDF The Strong Continuity Hypothesis: Evidence from Arabic-speaking

    supporting the Strong Continuity Hypothesis (Lust, 1999). Moreover, the results give evidence to Wexler's Hypothesis (1998), Very Early Knowledge of Inflection (VEKI), which says that children know the grammatical and phonological properties of inflections in a language in the earliest stages when t-word stage. Similarlyhey enter the two, this

  6. On Two Hypotheses of "Transfer" in L2A: Minimal Trees and Absolute L1

    This chapter presents evidence supporting the Strong Continuity Hypothesis in adult second language (L2) acquisition. It discusses that at all stage of acquisition, L2 learners have knowledge of the full inventory of both lexical and functional syntactic categories provided by Universal Grammar (UG). The chapter argues that the Weak Continuity ...

  7. Second Language Acquisition

    The strong continuity hypothesis in adult L2 acquisition of functional categories. In S. Flynn, G. Martohardjono and W. O'Neil (eds), The Generative Study of Second Language Acquisition (pp. 61-77). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Google Scholar Eubank, L. (1993/1994). On the transfer of parametric values in L2 development.

  8. Universal grammar: The strong continuity hypothesis in first language

    It is shown that the LSTM indeed abstracts new structures as learning proceeds, and the behaviour of the network is analysed over time using a novel methodology which consists in quantifying the level of grammatical abstraction in the model's generated output (its 'babbling'), compared to the language it has been exposed to.

  9. Functional projection of CP and phrase structure parametrization: An

    Functional projection of CP and phrase structure parametrization: An argument for the Strong Continuity Hypothesis. In B. Lust, M. Suñer, & J. Whitman (Eds.), Syntactic theory and first language acquisition: Cross-linguistic perspectives, Vol. 1.

  10. PDF Continuity in Linguistic Development: The Scope of Syntax and the

    Continuity Hypothesis (Tomasello, 2000). In this regard, we recently reported evidence ... display a strong preference for the interpretation of such sentences which corresponds to the surface syntactic position of the quantificational elements involved. This observation has been described under the label of 'isomorphism'

  11. A note on "continuity" of universal grammar: Reply to Cairns, McDaniel

    They therefore do not merit an independent "grammar type". Thus, on both theoretical and empirical grounds, we cannot consider McDaniel J.C. Sherman, B. Lust / Cognition 48 (1993) 195-197 197 and Cairns (1990) (and subsequent publications of this proposal) to be consistent with a "strong continuity hypothesis" for first language acquisition.

  12. On Continuity and the Emergence of Functional Categories in ...

    All Strong Continuity accounts seem to assume the two following tenets, implicitly or explicitly: (a) The functional structure of a child's ... Continuity Hypothesis is founded on the widely held theoretical assumption that the specifications of lexical categories are universal across languages, whereas the

  13. Syntactic Theory and First Language Acquisition

    Description. Universal Grammar (UG) is a theory of both the fundamental principles for all possible languages and the language faculty in the "initial state" of the human organism. These two volumes approach the study of UG by joint, tightly linked studies of both linguistic theory and human competence for language acquisition.

  14. The status of functional categories in child second language ...

    Weak Continuity hypothesis, for others - who postulate Strong Continuity in interlanguage grammars - functional categories and their projections are available in the early grammars of both adult and child L2 learners (e.g., Lakshmanan, 1993/94, Lakshmanan and Selinker, 1994; Schwartz and Sprouse, 1994, 1996; Gavruseva and

  15. The continuity hypothesis.

    A longstanding tradition exists, surveyed by Freud in the opening pages of his Interpretation of Dreams, holding that dream life is continuous with awake life. Contrary to Domhoff (2017), Freud partook of this tradition, and Calvin Hall, who was much influenced by Freud, articulated the idea in 1971 (with A. Bell) as "the continuity hypothesis." A decade later, with Domhoff's ...

  16. North East Linguistics Society

    The Syntax of CP and V-2 in Early Child German (ECG) The Strong Continuity Hypothesis K. Boser Cornell University B. Lust Cornell University L. Santelmann Cornell University J. Whitman Cornell University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/nels Part of the Linguistics Commons Recommended Citation

  17. Consciousness across Sleep and Wake: Discontinuity and Continuity of

    The continuity hypothesis posits that there is continuity, of some form, ... In cognitive psychology, this would represent a weak semantic association rather than a strong one, with the latter typically reflecting focused thought and goal-oriented processing. Hartmann, however, did not speculate as to what the function of such ...

  18. DreamResearch.net: Invasion of the Concept Snatchers (Domhoff, 2017)

    The mistaken redefinition of the continuity hypothesis has been translated into a strong indictment by dream researchers who see the continuity hypothesis as a "competitor" to their "threat simulation" and "social simulation" theories, both of which claim that dreams are rehearsals that are useful for dealing with future waking events (see ...

  19. The Continuity Hypothesis of Dreams: A More Balanced Account

    Thus the empirical support for some degree of continuity between dream content and waking life is strong. The database supporting the theory has been considerably strengthened by many dream ...

  20. The Strong Continuity Hypothesis: Evidence from Arabic-speaking

    In contrast to the previous hypotheses, the strong continuity hypothesis (SCH) (Lust, 1999) emphasizes the availability of complete functional structure from the initial state and conforms to the principles of Universal Grammar (UG). This hypothesis parallels the standard Government and Binding framework (Chomsky, 1982) in that all clauses are ...

  21. The Strong Continuity Hypothesis: Evidence from Arabic-speaking

    The paper argues that agreement inflections (person, number, gender) are available to children early, thereby supporting the Strong Continuity Hypothesis (Lust, 1999). Moreover, the results give ...

  22. PDF Chapter The Continuity Hypothesis

    apter 7The Continuity HypothesisThe idea that everyday good and bad moods might differ from clinically significant depression and mania only in terms of degree rather than kind suggests that these states are on continua such that intensification of norm. l processes can produce disorder. This view, sometimes referred to as the continuity ...

  23. Continuity Hypothesis

    The Continuity Hypothesis was put forward by John Bowlby (1953) as a critical effect of attachments in his development of Attachment Theory. ... (MLS) have shown strong support for the playing out of the internal working model in children's later relationships. In the MLS a cohort of children were followed from the age of 12 months to ...

  24. Timeliness criticality in complex systems

    Timeliness is a crucial property for the optimal functioning of socio-technical systems where delays can propagate. Now it is shown that a stylized model of delay propagation on temporal networks ...